Clarification of Some Ambiguities in Systemt

 

by Stephen Palmquist (stevepq@hkbu.edu.hk)

 

 

A. The Faculty of Representation

 

  Two ambiguities arise out of Kant's habit of referring to the 'faculty of representation'. The first concerns his frequent use of the word 'faculty'. This and many of the terms used in connection with it are often condemned by modern critics as reflecting Kant's unphilosophi­cal acceptance of 'the imagi­nary subject of transcendental psychology' [S17:97]. The only proper re­sponse, they say, is to 'de-psychologize' his theory in order to purify its truly philosophical content [H5:288]. And this, of course, involves analyzing the arguments in modern terms in hopes of finding consistent and/or conclusive bits of reasoning-a pro­cedure the interpretive value of which I have already assessed in I.1. In defense of Kant's general habit of using such unusual ter­minology, it should be noted that, although it appears to the twentieth-cen­tury reader as if he is arbitrarily inventing words at nearly every step, most of these terms were familiar to philosophers in Kant's own time. 'Indeed', Weldon tells us, 'it is not too much to say that all Kant's leading concep­tions ... and much of his greatly abused architectonic are clearly foreshadowed in the [works of his predecessors]' [W16:52; s.a. P2:1.100n and V4:82-8]. This alone, of course, does not justify our continued use of such terms; but it does suggest they are meaningful in their own context, so they cannot simply be discarded by the interpreter without seriously misrepresent­ing Kant's System.

 

  The specific reason why we should continue to use Kant's faculty termi­nology when interpreting his philosophy is that it is not, in fact, intended to be psychological. (Kant clearly distinguishes on several occasions between transcendental philosophy and empirical psychology [e.g., Kt1:152].) Instead, as Vleeschauwer points out, Kant's use of apparently psycho­log­ical terminol­ogy assumes a 'different perspective' [V4:88]. It is simply the way he has chosen to refer to the subjective functions of human knowing in his radically perspective-bound philosophy. Because philosophical analysis is al­ways lim­ited to one perspective at a time (at least, if it is to be coherent), the functions can be regarded as distinct even though each faculty performs its own function on 'one and the same territory of experience'.[1] Van de Pitte defends Kant in much the same way when he says:

 

Kant is unable to define sensibility (except as receptivity), the categories, or the imagination (except as the agency of synthesis).... [Yet] this inability does not at all trouble him. For ... it is not the faculties of the mind [as such] that he is concerned with, but the functions which must be fulfilled if experi­ence is to be possible. [V3:1024-5]

 

  The second ambiguity to be considered here is that the term 'repre­sen­ta­tion' can be used either as a verb to name an a priori function of know­ing, or as a noun to name the state of the object once it is determined by this func­tion. This means the effect on an object of the faculty of representation (i.e., of the function of representing) is to determine that it is a representation (i.e., a represented object) [cf. A11:21; F7:xxxi; P8:72-3]. The same ambigu­ity arises with many of Kant's other terms as well, and may explain, at least in part, why, as Wolff points out, 'statements about knowing and statements about knowledge tend to be interchangeable' for Kant [W21:73n]. Fortunate­ly, as long as both possible meanings are kept in mind, Kant's in­tentions can usually be determined from the context with a fair amount of cer­tainty.

 

  Perhaps in an attempt to avoid the ambiguity in this example, some translators and commentators translate Vorstellung as 'idea' rather than 'repre­sentation'. Although the word 'idea', when 'taken in the ordinary English sense' [P3:93n] is admittedly an accurate translation of Vorstellung, it is inappropriate when interpreting Kant for several reasons: (1) Deliberate ambi­gu­ity in the original should be preserved, as far as possible, in an accu­rate translation. Substituting 'idea' in some passages takes away the possibil­ity of interpreting Vorstellung as referring to a mental function, since 'idea' does not also mean 'act of having an idea'. (2) Vorstellung has such a wide variety of applications for Kant that the rather narrow word 'idea' is too specific in many contexts. (3) Kant has an­other technical term (Idee) which must be translated 'idea'. Since he does not intend to identify Vorstellung and Idee, it is misleading to use the same word in translating both. As Kant himself pleads: 'I beseech those who have the interests of philosophy at heart ... [to] be careful to preserve the expression "idea" [Idee] in its original meaning, that it may not become one of those ex­pressions which are commonly used to indicate any and every species of rep­resentation [Vorstellung]' [Kt1:376]. To avoid confusion, therefore, whenever a text which renders Kant's Vorstellung as 'idea' (or any word other than 'representation') is quoted in this book, I have substituted the word 'representation' without further notice.

 

  The suggestion that Vorstellung should be translated as 'presenta­tion' [W8:192; H4:xi; P14:27n] would be suitable when it is used in the context of the original representation which arises in the first step of systemt; but in all of its other uses, the 're' connotes a repeated determination of the same ob­ject, and should therefore be preserved. Rotenstreich's rendering of the term as 'image' [R11:134], however, is wholly unacceptable, except perhaps in steps four and seven, where representation takes the form of imagination.

 

B. Placement of the Transcendental Object in Systemt

 

  Another source of possible confusion is that Kant discusses his doctrine of the transcendental object more in the Analytic than in the Aesthetic [see note VI.8], yet I have placed it in the first stage of systemt [see VII.2.A]. That   it belongs in the first stage should be evident in light of its medi­at­ing role between the thing in itself and the various determinate forms of rep­re­sen­ta­tion [cf. VI.2]. As Kant says in Kt6:218n, 'the architect of a system' must begin by positing 'an object as such' as the basis for all other divisions. Moreover, it would not make sense to place it after sensibility, since Kant clearly says in Kt1:522-3 that 'this transcen­dental object ... is given in itself prior to all experience.' This orig­­inal representation differs from representa­tions which consti­tute appear­ances, inasmuch as it remains 'necessarily un­known' [523-4]. Thus, the tran­scendental object is a pre-intuitive represen­ta­tion of sensibility in much the same way that a perception is a pre-conceptual representation of the under­standing.

 

  Some interpreters have recognized, in varying degrees, the connection between the transcendental object and the first stage of systemt. Gotterbarn alludes to its primary position in the logical order of Kant's theory when he says it 'is a preliminary concept which prepares for the conception of "affinity" and the transcendental deduction of the categories' [G11:199]. Buchdahl insists it 'is the central notion with which to begin' in interpreting systemt [B27:52]; its 'essential function is ... as the starting point of realiza­tion procedure which involves, to begin with, sensibility' [78]. Weldon con­nects it with sensibility by saying 'the transcendental object is not itself a possible object of knowl­edge. It denotes simply the formal characteristics which render intelligible the manifold of pure or empirical sensibility, the ground of synthetic unity in phenomena' [W16:178n]. Likewise, Walsh refers to the transcendental object as 'awaiting application ... [to] the data of the senses' [W9:162; see Kt1: A394,411n]. All these comments suggest that there is an important sense in which the transcendental object lies at the very basis of the Aesthetic, even though it is not discussed at length therein.

 

  Kant employs the concept of the transcendental object in the argu­ments of his second, third and fourth stages primarily as a way of re­ferring to the influences of the first stage on the others. That is, the concept of the tran­scendental object stands for the assumption that some Aesthetic element (i.e., some experience in general) is given, without presupposing anything about its intuitive or sensible character. Thus in Kt1:A290 Kant says 'the concept of an object in general [is] taken problematically, without its having been decided whether it is something or nothing.' The first step, however, is con­cerned not so much with the concept of the transcendental object as with the transcendental object itself-i.e., with that radically undetermined state of objects (as such), which confirms the reality of their existence. Thus, Bird is correct when he says Kant devotes more attention to the concept of the tran­scendental object than to the transcendental object itself [B20:5]; but this does not necessarily mean the former is more important to the system. On the con­trary, the tran­scendental object is an element in systemt, whereas its con­cept is not.

 

  The transcendental object, being itself neither a concept nor an intuition, must therefore lie at the base of both the Aesthetic and the Analytic of Kt1. It could be called 'the ultimate recipient of all the predicates we bear', in the sense that it is equal and opposite to the giver of all predicates (the transcen­dental subject). Kant could have made this more clear by naming the pre-Logic section of Kt1 'Transcendental Sensibility', and including in it first a chapter on 'Transcendental Object', to be followed by the existing 'Transcen­dental Aes­thetic' as Chapter Two. This would have shown that the tran­scen­dental object is not part of the Aesthetic, any more than it is part of (i.e., an element in) the Analytic.[2]

 

C. Mathematical Judgments

 

  Kant uses the assumption that mathematical judgments depend on pure intuition [see note VII.16] to argue for the intuitive nature of time and space. The inadequacy of this approach is often emphasized by commentators [see e.g., Pq18:1.3]; but Parsons points out that this is a 'comparatively acciden­tal feature of Kant's view' [P1:38], for the validity of his theory of time and space is not necessarily dependent on the validity of his conception of geome­try. Unfortunately, in defending the intuitive nature of time and space Kant does argue from the assumption that the judgments of mathematics, as well as those of physics and metaphysics, have a synthetic a priori status [Kt1:14-8]. His claims have often been debated, and not infrequently rejected [B5:18-21; R12:145; but cf. P14:6-7 and H16:376; s.a. W17:17-27]; but inasmuch as they are not constitutive elements of systemt, I shall merely offer a brief suggestion for a possible interpretation.

 

  Mathematical truth-claims could be synthetic when viewed from the em­pir­ical perspective of judgments, as, for example, when considering how to go about solving a particular problem [cf. M3:26-7], yet analytic when viewed from the logical perspective of how to prove the validity of a given proposi­tion. (In K2:10.528-30(Z1:129-30) Kant draws a similar distinction between viewing mathematical concepts 'subjective­ly' as 'a task to be done' or 'objec­tively' as a 'proof', though he does not apply this to the analytic-synthetic distinction.) For instance, given the laws of mathematics, the num­ber '12' does contain in it analytically the addition of '7' and '5'; neverthe­less, if a person thinks of the numbers '7' and '5', he does not ipso facto think of the number '12' until the notion of 'addition' and other relevant laws of mathe­mat­ics are specified [see Kt1:14-7,740-66; cf. W5:162-3]. Thus, as Beck asserts, in order to establish the validity of a mathematical claim, there must be an 'intuitive construction of the concept' [B5:19; cf. P2:2.129-31]-and this pre­supposes at least that the synthetic method has been adopted. I discuss the nature of mathematical knowledge and its relation to Kant's doc­trine of pure intuition in greater detail in Pq8:14-22, Pq9:279-82 and Pq14.

 

D. Inner and Outer Sense

 

  Kant's reasons for giving priority to the transcendental necessity of time and inner sense in stage one are not always clear; but in later stages-especially in the second edition of Kt1-he balances this one-sidedness with a cor­responding emphasis on the empirical necessity of space and outer sense [e.g., Kt1:156]. Strawson regards this balance between the inner and the outer as one of the crucial aspects of Kant's transcendental idealism, for it insures that 'no superiority of status, as regards reality or certainty of existence' can be accorded 'to states of consciousness over physical objects' [S17:21].

 

  Unfortunately, the precise meaning of these terms, particularly of 'inner sense', is difficult to determine. Kant does express the 'opinion' in Kt14: 60(94) that 'the secret faculty ... by which judgment is possible ... is noth­ing but the power of the internal sense, that is, the power of making our own rep­resentations the object of our thoughts.' Conceived in these terms, inner sense would seem to be a reflection of the means by which stage one is re­lated to the concepts which arise in stage two [but cf. note VII.25]. Similar­ly, outer sense could be regarded as the means by which stage one is related to the phenomenal objects which will arise in stage three. (That stage four is not so closely connected with stage one is accurately reflected in Figure VII.3 by their correlation with the opposing ++ and -- components, respectively.)

 

  Much of the confusion arising out of Wolff's discussion of these terms in W21:191-202 stems from his own failure to see that 'inner sense' and 'outer sense' are two ways of considering the contents of sensibility, and that their empirical manifestation is something quite apart from their function in the transcendental conditions of knowing. According to Wolff's empirical in­ter­pretation, 'inner sense' denotes 'an inner perception of the spatial manifold which constitutes the contents of consciousness' [199]; likewise, Weldon rejects the idea that inner sense refers to a kind of 'feeling' of oneself [W16: 152], equating it instead with 'my own past acts of awareness'-i.e., memory [154-5]. Kant himself refers in Kt30:284(69) to 'inward experience' as involving 'an awareness of one's psychological state.' But this empiri­cal inter­preta­tion is not incompatible with Kemp Smith's transcendental interpre­ta­tion: 'The representations of outer sense are all by their very nature like­wise representations of inner sense. To outer sense is due both their content and their spatial form; to inner sense they owe only the additional form of time' [K3:294]. Given the perspectival ori­entation of Kant's philosophy, these two positions are quite compatible.

 

  The failure to recognize the perspectival basis of Kant's System leads many interpreters to reject his theory of inner and outer sense prematurely, on the grounds that 'time is an abstraction from what is concrete fact or events' [E3:190], and is therefore 'a condition of there being a finite mind', but not vice versa [186; s.a. B17:156-9]. In our discussion of stage three (especially of the schematism in step seven) we saw that Kant is in full agreement with this view of empirical reality. Nevertheless, this does not preclude the possi­bility (or reduce the necessity) of viewing time transcendentally as a formal condition imposed by the subject, as in stage one. In any case, Kant's theory of time and space is clear enough so that a psychologist recently referred to patients suffering from 'akinesia' (inability to function physically and/or men­tally in time or space) as having 'a "Kantian" delirium, and ultimate akinesia as being "aKantia"' [S1:252]!

 

  The arguments of Swinburne in S19:26-40 and Quinton in Q3:130-46 against Kant's theory that there can be only one space suffer from a similar neglect of the principle of perspective. The fact that it is logically possible to imagine in a philosophical thought-experiment that two unrelated spaces exist (one of which, for example, could be heaven [S19:40]) is advanced as evidence that Kant is mistaken [28,37; Q3:143]. But Kant does not deny the logical consistency of such a proposal, nor even its real possibility; what he denies is that more than one space can be known to be the transcendental ground for the coherent, unified experience of one rational individual. Neither argument disproves this transcendental claim. On the contrary, Quinton's thought-experi­ment posits two coherent, unified, but unrelated (and unrelat­able!) sets of ex­periences; and Swinburne ends up admitting that 'we have no reliable infor­mation' about any space other than our own [S19:40].

 

E. Forms of Imagination

 

  Kant's theory of imagination plays an important role in both editions of Kt1 [J4:686]; but he obscures this role by developing the theory differently in each. In the second edition, for instance, he several times prefers the term 'figurative synthesis' to denote 'the transcendental synthesis of imagination' [Kt1:151,154], and suggests that in a sense 'the imagination ... belongs to sen­sibility' even though it is a function of understanding [151-2; cf. note IX.1]. What makes matters worse is that in both editions of section one of the Deduction [116-29], as Paton contends, Kant's 'doctrine of imagination is un­doubt­edly inconsistent with the doctrine expressed elsewhere' [P2:1.53]. But in Y1 Young provides a good analysis of many of the problems sur­round­ing Kant's view of the imagination.

 

  The relationship between perception and imagination can help us to dis­tinguish more clearly between two types of imagination, as well as between imagination and the other types of synthesis [cf. note VII.38]. Kant some­times refers to the transcendental faculty of imagination as the 'productive imagination' in order to clarify the difference between it and its empirical counterpart, which he usually calls 'the reproduc­tive faculty of imagination'. The reproductive imagination 'leads the mind to reinstate a preceding percep­tion alongside the subsequent perception ..., and so to form whole series of perceptions' [Kt1:A121]; only in this way can perceptions be experienced as appearances in time. It is also responsible for the more common use of 'imagination', in which the reproductive imagination acts as 'the faculty of representing in intui­tion an object which is not itself present' [151; s.a. Kt66:153(32)]. Whereas the productive imagination produces the original syn­thetic unity of the manifold and is objectively valid (i.e., a priori), the re­pro­ductive imagination simply reproduces particular images of a perception, and thus 'has only subjective validity' (i.e., it is a posteriori) [Kt1:141,152; see note VII.3].

 

  In its most elementary form the consciousness aroused through the syn­thetic function of the productive imagination, when it is 'immediate­ly directed upon perceptions', is entitled 'apprehension' [Kt1:A120]. This aspect of syn­thesis, Kant explains, 'is only a placing together of the manifold of empirical intuition' [129] by which the imagination prepares the manifold of sensation for the actual process of synthesis [235]. In fact, the whole first stage of systemt is implicitly included in apprehension when that stage is viewed in stage two from the (logical) perspective of the use to be made of it by the imagination. Although apprehension has an empirical application [see e.g., 164], it is also transcendental in the sense that it represents the initial activity of the function of the productive imagination. Kant may have introduced these extra terms to allow for the logical possibility that imagination's syn­thesis might produce something other than apprehended perceptions, or that there might be a manifold which is not synthesiz­able [E5:110-1]. But if em­pirical knowledge is to result, it is necessary for the synthesis of productive imagina­tion to give rise to apprehended perceptions [Kt1:246].

 

  This necessary epistemological connection may be what persuaded Kant to propose in the first edition of Kt1 his rather ambiguous theory of a three­fold syn­thesis, made up of intuitive apprehension, imaginative re­production and con­ceptual recognition [A98-111]. Although he claims at times that these terms can denote transcendental syntheses [A100,102], he admits elsewhere that the distinctions are 'merely empirical elements of experience' [A125]. In either case the first and third terms are apparently intended to describe the in­fluence of synthesis on what pre­cedes (viz., intuitions) and follows (viz., con­cepts) the actual function of synthesis in imagination (i.e., in step four). Thus, when its close connection with the synopsis (i.e., sensation) given in stage one is in view, the phrase 'synthesis of apprehension in intuition' [A98] simply indi­cates that synthesis presupposes the apprehension of a sen­sible object in step three [162n,237]. Likewise, with respect to the conceptual goal towards which step four heads, 'synthesis of recognition in a concept' [A103] simply indicates that synthesis prepares the way for conception in step five [cf. H11:183]. (Paton agrees that Kant should have made a point of clarifying that 'recognition involves under­standing or apperception' [P2:1.379; but cf. Kt1:A115]. Elsewhere he makes the interesting suggestion that the first three categories correspond to this threefold synthesis [P2:2.56-7n].) And the sec­ond member of this threesome, 'the synthesis of reproduc­tion in imagination' [Kt1:A100], has already been accounted for as the empir­ical counterpart of productive imagination. In the second edition of Kt1 Kant, apparently real­izing the redundancy of this three­fold synthesis, concentrates more on the simple fact that synthesis as such is a necessary condition of knowing.

 

F. Categories and Conceptual Schemes

 

  Before arguing in the Transcendental Deduction for the necessity of categorial conception as the fifth condition of knowing, Kant lists and briefly de­scribes each of his twelves choices for categories in the passage known as the Metaphysical Deduction [Kt1:91-116]. He asserts that 'the function of thought in judgment can be brought under four heads': quantity, quality, rela­tion and modality [95], each of which in turn has 'three moments' [see Table III.7]. The table in which Kant lists the resulting twelve functions is some­times called Kant's 'Table of Judgments' [see e.g., S21:3-19], even though Kant himself never uses this phrase in Kt1. This practise stems, no doubt, from the fact that Kemp Smith's translation uses this phrase as a page head­ing on two pages. Yet this label is highly misleading, since the initial table does not list the forms of judgment (which would belong in stage three), but 'the mere form of understanding' as abstracted from judgment [95]. Kant him­self refers to the table as 'the table of logical functions' [112], so this more accurate name is the one interpreters ought to use.

 

  Kant then proceeds to list in a 'Table of Categories' the twelve 'pure con­cepts of the understanding' which correspond to the twelve 'logical functions' [Kt1:105-6]. This new table differs from the first in being slightly less ab­stract: whereas the first lists only a set of bare 'logical functions', the second specifies the pure concepts through which each function can be applied to ap­pearances in order to produce empirical knowledge [143; s.a. E2:178]. But for both Kant claims a kind of certainty and completeness [see e.g., Kt2:322-6] which has seemed rather presumptuous to most interpreters. He decrees, for example, that the logical functions listed in the first table 'specify the under­stand­ing completely, and yield an exhaustive inventory of its powers' [Kt1: 105]. Hence, there need never be 'any addition to the transcendental table of categories, as if it were in any respect imperfect' [115]. Not only can this table 'reveal and make noticeable every gap in the understanding' [265], but it will also, he predicts, supply 'the complete plan of a whole science' [109].

 

  Despite the ostentatious nature of such assertions, Kant devotes little ef­fort in Kt1 to the defense of his twelve categories or to the clarification of their individual meanings [but see Kt10:101-9(106-16)]. Instead he boasts: 'In this treatise, I purposely omit the definitions of the categories' [Kt1:108], though he later confesses that 'we are un­able to define them even if we wished' [A241]. (Some commentators have attempted to defend and/or refine Kant's choices [see e.g., E2:148-94; E5:137-40; P2:1.295-6]-a worthy cause which we need not join here.) The fact that he never even explains the nature of their twelvefold structure-a task I have attempted in III.3-has given rise to the commonly held opinion that Kant 'was stupid to the point of perversity in the detail of his doctrine of categories' [M2:213; cf. 244-5]. Yet the justifica­tion for such neglect is that the categories only obtain 'reality' when their 'application' is taken into account [see Kt7:385]; and Kant does eventually support his initial dogmatic account by examining in the third stage of systemt the principles through which each category is applied in producing empirical knowledge [see VII.3.A].

 

  Although critics are often quick to point out the absurdity of Kant's claim that his own particular choice of twelve categories is universally valid for all time, they are usually slow to suggest any alternatives. Strawson, for example, takes it for granted that our 'schemes of thought ... are not static schemes, but allow of ... indefinite refinement', just as in all sciences or in the 'development of social forms' [S17:44]. Martin goes so far as to call Kant's view 'pitiful' [M3:82], suggesting that the one point of agreement between all inter­preters of Kant has been 'that this rigid structure has got to be made dy­namic and living.' He suggests this could be done by emphasizing that, in spite of the 'static' form of his tables, 'Kant's aim [was] to free him­self from a static conception' by regarding the categories as 'funda­mental acts of pure thought' [M3:81]. Walker, by contrast, claims Kant's choices are 'not so arbi­trary and artificial as is sometimes made out' [W2:26]-a claim sup­ported by our findings in III.3, which suggest it may be more important to insist on the necessity of there being twelve categories, than to insist on Kant's choices being necessarily correct for everyone everywhere. Premature rejection of Kant's table of categor­ies can be avoided by recognizing they are not intended to function like a scheme of 'social forms', or of any empirical science, but merely as a bare, architectonic structure defining the logical relations implicit in all thinking.

 

  Kant does actually explain quite clearly that the certainty of his table rests on its formal structure. Thus, for example, he says 'the third category in each class always arises from the combination of the second category with the first' [Kt1:110; s.a. Kt2:325n; K2:10.344(Z1:112)]. We have already dis­cussed at length some of its other formal features in III.3. Once its formal structure is recognized as the source of its certainty and completeness, we can allow that other types of 'conceptual schemes' (as they are usually called nowadays) might be able to produce empirical knowledge (as it is understood in other cul­tures or societies), but that such alternative schemes will be com­plete only when they are described in terms of this same twelvefold form. A Kantian response to such a proposal would be that modern talk of concep­tual schemes nearly always assumes the Empirical Perspective, whereas his Table of Categories assumes the Transcendental Perspective, inasmuch as it defines the set of conditions which must be met by any viable conceptual scheme (whether it be animistic, astrological, reli­gious, Newtonian, relativistic or any other).

 

  The main purpose of Kant's arguments in the Analytic of Concepts is to establish the formal status of categories as a necessary condition for empirical knowledge, so he focuses in the Transcendental Deduction only on their general function. As a result, many interpreters have pointed out that, as Körner puts it in K9:57, 'even if his proof of the complete list of Categories was not successful he may still claim to have established that we do apply Categories in making objective empiri­cal judgments.' Although Körner is right to dis­tinguish the validity of the Transcendental Deduction from that of the Metaphysical Deduction, he unfortunately assumes Kant was trying to prove his categories in the Metaphysical Deduction; yet this is open to con­siderable doubt. Why would Kant wish to prove their validity, when the pure categories as such are, in Paton's words, 'of no use at all', being 'merely the pure form of the use of understanding' [P2:2.438; cf. Kt2:324]? Kant's proofs for his choice of catego­ries really come only in the Analytic of Principles.

 

  Because Kant does not actually present conclusive proofs concerning the nature of each category until the section on the Principles, Wolff suggests: 'The principles are not applications of the categories ...; they are the cate­gories' [W21:204]. But this completely ignores the difference in perspective between the second and third stages. The categories function as the condition through which knowledge relating to the logical perspective is synthetically realized, while the principles function as the condition which determines the form of knowledge relating to the empirical perspective. Given this differ­ence, we should expect to find Kant defending each in a different manner.

 

  Another problem is that Kant does not always clearly explain just how he intends us to think of these categories as applying to appear­ances. For in­stance, do they all apply to every appearance, or does each appearance reveal only one (or several) of the categories? Kant sometimes seems to suggest the latter, as when he says 'All the manifold ... is determined in respect of one of the logical functions of judgment' [Kt1:143e.a.]. But Paton argues that all twelve 'forms of thought must be present in every judgment' [P2:1.226n; s.a. 212-5; E2:194; E5:147-8]. In contrast to both of these extreme views, I believe Kant wishes us to think of each judgment as being determined by one of the three 'moments' or logical functions listed under each of the four head­ings, so that each judgment will have precisely four categorial characteristics deter­mining its form.

 

G. Varieties of Deduction

 

  One of the most complicated aspects of Kant's exposition concerns the various sorts of 'deduction' to which he refers. The difference between the Metaphysical and Transcendental deductions of the categories was mentioned in Appendix VII.F [s.a. note III.17]. Two further com­plications are also worth discussing: the difference between the first and sec­tion versions of the Tran­scendental Deduction; and the difference between Kant's so-called 'objec­tive' and 'subjective' deductions.

 

  I have, for the most part, played down the many differences between the first and second editions of the Transcendental Deduction. This is not because the differences are of no significance, but rather, because the most significant points Kant wants to get across are the arguments which actually constitute the three steps in stage two; and these must be present in both versions, since Kant claims in Kt1:xxxvii that 'in the form and completeness of the [archi­tec­tonic] plan, I have found no­thing to alter' in the second edition. Neverthe­less, the second edition is a slight improvement over the first in the sense that it reveals these three steps more clearly, with fewer digressions into side issues [see e.g., note VII.34 and Ap. VII.E].

 

  In the opening pages of Kt1 [Axvi-xvii] Kant distinguishes 'two sides' of his inquiry. The 'subjective deduction' investigates the nature and possibility of 'the cognitive faculties' of the understand­ing; it is of secondary importance and gives the appearance of being 'somewhat hypothetical in character'. But the 'objective deduction', which 'is intended to expound and render intelligible the objective validity of [the] a priori concepts' of the understanding, he regards as the 'essential' purpose of his inquiry. Because Kant himself never specifies exactly how or where he develops these two sides in his exposition, Weldon is probably right to say 'there is no point in attempting such a dis­tinction' in an interpretation [W16:173n]. Nevertheless, interpreters have sometimes made use of it in various ways. Strawson, for example, identifies the 'subjective deduction' with Kant's 'transcendental psychology', and attempts to 'disentangle' it from the truly philosophical 'objective deduction' in order to discard the former [S17:16; cf. H11:171]. In sharp contrast to this approach, Wolff equates Section 2 [Kt1:A95-114] with the subjective and Section 3 [A115-130] with the objective deduction [W21:85,100,164], and contends that the former 'is the key to the interpretation of the entire Critique' [80]. (See also E3:97; O3:149-67; P4:175-8; V4:84-5.)

 

  From the little Kant does say about this distinction, it could be argued, in contrast to these interpretations, that the subjective deduction is the argu­ment of the entire second stage and that the objective deduction, though al­luded to at various points in the Analytic of Concepts, is in fact the argument of the third stage [cf. H13:75]. This alternate interpretation is sup­ported by Kant's stress on 'objective validity' in step seven, as well as in the remainder of the third stage. Such an interpretation can help us to see how the two de­ductions, as 'two sides to the same argument' [W2:83], are actually mutually dependent upon each other [cf. E5:70,85 and P2:1.529].

 

H. Schematism

 

  Some commentators interpret Kant's statements concerning the reciproc­ity between intuition and conception to mean 'there is no third operation besides thinking and sensing, all knowledge being for [Kant] covered by these two' [E5:36; s.a. E3:98]. Schematism can then be either rejected as superflu­ous, or regarded as nothing but a return to intuition by the concept. Allison follows Gram's arguments to this effect by equating pure intuition with schemata [A7:86-88,104; cf. H11:96-7], though he rejects Gram's claim that this is incompatible with Kant's notion of the schema as a hybrid 'third thing' [A7:88]. Bennett, by contrast, offers a rather different sort of reduction: 'The schema of any empirical concept is just the concept itself' [B17:151].

 

  The fact that Kant has already established a close connection between the first two stages has led some commentators (such as Adickes and Kemp Smith) to regard the whole Schematism chapter as repetitive and unneces­sary. To this Paton rightly rebuts: 'It is vital to Kant's argument to specify the transcendental schema which is contained in each catego­ry' [P2:2.68]; in­deed, it is 'absolutely essential' [76]. For, whether or not there really is a third thing such as the schema, as Kant himself may have believed, is not as im­portant as the fact that there must be some third function. The functions of intuition and conception in isolation are not sufficient to explain how em­piri­­cal knowledge arises: for that, a third function, that of combining these two functions in a whole (i.e., schematism) is necessary. As long as we recog­nize the new and different use in stage three of that which first arises in stage two (viz., synthesis and concepts), we can agree with Deleuze when he claims that, just as understanding judges by means of its concepts, so also imagina­tion schematizes by means of its syntheses [D2:18]. Synthesis is pre-concep­tual in step four, but post-conceptual in step seven.

 

  Vaihinger and others have assumed the activity of schematism must be an example of a so-called 'noumenal act', inasmuch as the function of reintro­ducing time cannot itself be an act in time. Paton rejects this interpretation, arguing instead that such a synthetic process must take time [P2:2.393]. Perhaps a better solution would be to say that this whole question is incoher­ent. As a transcendental function, its place in the chronological sequence of events is not at issue; it is not an 'act' in any literal sense (phenomenal or noumenal), but a logically necessary function. As temporal functions, intu­i­tion, conception and schematism are all mixed up in a 'bundle', not unlike Hume's, and cannot ordinarily be isolated as discrete acts.

 

  After noting its inscrutability, Chipman speculates that the schema may be what physicalists are looking for when they investigate neural mechanisms [C7:115]. But Dahlstrom, recognizing that empirical schemata may well be obscure, insists the schematism of pure concepts, with which Kant is primar­ily concerned, 'must be both scrutable and neces­sary' [D1:220]. He argues against those who believe that, because the condition for knowing a concept is being able to apply it correctly, concept and schema are always equivalent (e.g., Bennett [B17:142-51], Warnock [W11:77-82], and Wilkerson [W20:94-5]), by pointing out that 'a schema provides a condition for cognition [viz., time] by means of a concept, not supplied by the concept itself' [D1:219]. He adds that such critics 'too often demand either the sort of knowledge Kant reserves for funda­mental principles (Grundsätze) or the knowledge Kant attributes to God.'

 

I. Principles

 

  The scholarly discussion of Kant's principles is so massive as to fill a small library all on its own. There have been many attempts to revise or reconstruct some or all of his arguments in various ways. Strawson, for instance, at­tempts to reconstruct Kant's 'analogies of experience' by regarding perma­nence, cause, and interrelatedness not as 'absolutely indispensable ele­ments in terms of which we see the world if we are to see an objective world at all', but rather as 'natural hopes' which or­dinarily characterize our experi­ence [S17:146]. Of course, much hinges in such a revision on just what the word 'ordi­nar­ily' is taken to mean. This is especially true because Kant him­self claims the principles determine not, as Strawson's wording seems to sug­gest, the way we see the world, but only the way we attain ordinary theoretical knowledge about the world. Kant would argue, no doubt, that Strawson's attempt to transfer the principles to the judicial standpoint of hope [see IX.1] would render the possibility of real theoretical knowledge hopeless!

 

  Interestingly, Kant defends something not unlike his three analo­gies in one of his first philosophical essays, where he argues that 'any substance which is cut off from connection with others is incapable of any change', which is an 'absurdity' [Kt11:409(243)e.a.]. To this 'principle of determining reason' he adds 'the principle of succession' [410-2(245-8)] and 'the principle of co-existence' [412-6(248-529], thus insuring that 'all things are found con­joined in a universal mutual connection' [413(248)]. But this essay differs from his mature position in at least two respects: first, he refers to these as 'principles of abstract metaphysical knowl­edge' [416(252)] instead of as nec­es­sary conditions for the possibility of experience; and secondly, he 'secures' his argument for 'mutual reciprocity' by appealing to 'the divine idea' [413 (248)] rather than by constructing a transcendental argument.

 

  Among Kant's principles, the 'postulates of empirical thought' are per­haps the most difficult to pin down, since 'modality ... contributes nothing to the content of the judgment' [Kt1:99-100]. Paton suggests that possibility, actuality and necessity correspond directly to the other three categories (viz., quantity, quality and relation, respec­tively) [P2:2.57]; in both cases the third member acts as the synthesis of the previous two [see 2.338n,341]. In K2:11.45(Z1:147-8) Kant gives one of his most concise accounts of what is entailed by the postulates, from which we can construct the following table:

 

Table Ap. VII.1: The Postulates as Forms of Judgment

 

  A common mistake among interpreters is to ignore the perspectival difference between the categories and the principles. Because he ignores this dif­ference, Rosenberg fails to see how Kant subsumes individual empirical instances under such general concepts [R9:349-60]. Yet the entire third stage of systemt is intended to provide just such an explanation. Likewise, England claims that because the categories (a term he uses to cover the principles as well) are not 'constitutive factors in the

object, but notions employed in the act of apprehension' [E3:103], 'their signifi­cance lies in the realm of knowl­edge', not in 'the realm of existent fact' [110]. Yet this ignores the fact that, as far as empirical objects are concerned, Kant believes the realm of fact must be located within the the realm of knowledge. Thus, England's complaint that Kant gives 'no justification whatsoever ... for supposing that the cate­gories enter into [the] very structure' of 'empirical things' [109] is unjustified for two reasons. First, the categories are merely logical forms, so they do not as such constitute objects. And secondly, the supposition that principles consti­tute objects [see note VII.49] does not require a separate justification, since it is part of the general Copernican Perspective upon which the entire Critical philosophy is built! The justification, then, is in part [see V.1] the coherence of the System to which this assumption gives rise.

 

J. Ideas

  In some respects, Kant's treatment of the ideas of reason resembles his treatment of the thing in itself (a similarity which will be treated more fully in Pq20 [cf. Ch. X]). The latter denotes the unknowable substratum (0) of the phenomenal world, whereas the former denotes the way we con­ceive of this real­ity (+++) as it impinges on our empirical judgments. For exam­ple, con­cern­ing the principle of substance, Kant says: 'The simplicity and other prop­er­ties of substance are intended to be only schema of this regulative principle and are not presupposed as being the actual ground of the properties of the soul' [Kt1:711]; to assume the latter would be to confuse the idea with the thing in itself.

 

  Kant criticizes Plato for conflating the roles of the idea and the thing in itself [Kt1:370-5]. Plato regarded ideas as 'the original causes of things' [374], whereas Kant believes they should be regarded only as 'ends' [375]. Rosenberg is therefore unfair to Kant when he says 'Kant misunderstood the nature of the Platonic Ideas and took them to be conceptual forms of knowl­edge when in fact they are absolutely non-conceptual' [R8:285]. Kant is well aware of Plato's sense of 'idea', and regards it as, for the most part, worthy of 'respect and imitation' [Kt1:375]; but he intentionally replaces Plato's use of the term with his own, narrower use. Kant's main complaint is against any­one who, like Plato, tends to use the word to include too much [376], espe­cially when it is regarded not just as a tool to regulate the way we think about an unknowable mystery, but also as itself constituting that reality and/or our knowledge of it.

 

 



 [1] Kt7:175. Thus, when comparing understanding and reason Kant says 'neither can interfere with the other' [175; cf. Kt1:33]. The importance of distinguishing each function is especially evident when Kant explains that 'error is brought about solely by the unobserved influence of sensibility on the understanding' [350].

 

 [2]  I am thankful to Rollin Workman for helping me to clarify many of the points raised in this section in a series of letters.

 

 

Send comments to the author: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

Back to the Table of Contents for this book.

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published books.

Back to the main map of Steve Palmquist's web site.