Kant's Theocentric Metaphysics

 

 

Prof. Stephen Palmquist, D.Phil. (Oxon)

Department of Religion and Philosophy

Hong Kong Baptist University

(stevepq@hkbu.edu.hk)

 

      Does Kant destroy the possibility of theology? Does he seek to undermine its legitimacy, or limit it to a merely negative path, by abolishing its metaphys­ical foundation? Does he substitute for metaphysics a positivistic theory of scientific knowledge which not only denies any hope of attaining knowledge of the transcendent, but also denies scientists themselves any true knowledge of the world as it is? Does he seek to undermine organized religion and the religious experience of countless individuals by reducing these to nothing but morality? The answers given to such questions will depend on what one believes Kant intended to accomplish in constructing his philosophy. Unfortunately, they have been answered all too often in ways that go directly against Kant's own expressed intentions.

 

      Many theologians, especially since Ritschl and the "back to Kant" move­ment, have tended to give affirmative answers, interpret­ing Kant "as an an­ti­meta­physical moralist" [B1:655].[1] On the basis of the "fact-value" distinction which Kant's philosophy appears to support, such neo-Kantians believed that if theol­ogy (like any other form of speculation) is to survive, it must cut all ties with metaphysics and perhaps even, following Barth's lead, with philosophy as a whole. Whatever view on the relation between theology and philosophy a per­son holds, anyone who interprets Kant in this way is sure to agree with Cupitt that "we who live after Kant must walk the negative way" [C4:57]. Collins adopts this position in C1:183 when he portrays Kant as "destroying ev­ery philosophy of God" and as arguing that "[n]atural theology has no possibility of providing us with true knowledge about God and should be abandoned."

 

      Philosophers too have often agreed in assessing the Critique of Pure Reason [Kt4], at least, as "the most thorough and devastating of all anti-metaphysical writings" [W2:38]. Shortly after the publication of the first Critique, Mendelssohn labelled Kant the "all destroyer"; and since then many have fol­lowed him in regarding Kant as "the arch-destroyer in the realm of thought", putting forward "destructive, world-annihilating thoughts" [H3:109]. Gilson ex­tends this judgment to the whole of Kant's philosophy, maintaining that "Kant...had no metaphysical interests of his own" [G3:310]. Since "a new philo­sophical cycle was to begin" [220] with Kant's thoroughgoing "rejection of metaphysics" [229], Gilson regards any of Kant's theories or statements which border on the metaphysical as superfluous nonessentials which he merely bor­rowed "from hearsay".[2] Findlay sums up this tendency rather concisely: "It is usual nowadays to think of Kant as some sort of incipient positivist, always verging towards a belief in the total non-significance of ideas lacking all empiri­cal illustration" [F1:3].

 

      Not all philosophers and theologians, however, interpret Kant's intentions so negatively. Findlay himself goes on to say that, even though "Kant's theory of knowledge...has aspects that can with justice be called ‘positivist', it is not at all positivist in its account of the necessary underpinnings of such knowledge" [F2:5]; "Kant's theory of knowledge cannot, therefore, be called positivist, though it is quite right to see something like positivism in his account of what we can effectively know" [9]. Barth agrees that it is wrong to view Kant as "a kind of super-sceptic", or as the "all-annihilating one"; for his criticism is al­ways intended as "an affirmation of reason.... Kant both has and demands an al­most unconditional faith in reason" [B1:270-1; cf. W6:16]. England adds that it is "only the validity of a certain type of metaphysics" which Kant denies [E1:207], for "what is really implied in the critical position is...the substitution of an immanent metaphysics for the older transcendent metaphysics" [113-4]. And Wood goes so far as to suggest that "Kant himself was in many ways...an ‘existentialist' theologian" [W6:150]![3]

 

      Numerous of Kant's own comments could be construed as defending a posi­tivism of some sort. For example, he urges us "to believe that we have approx­imated to completeness in the empirical employment of [a] principle only in proportion as we are in a position to verify such unity in empirical fashion" [Kt4:720, emphasis added]. If this is positivism, however, it is far from straight­forward; for he continues with the caveat: "a completeness which is never, of course, attainable." Moreover, when Kant turns away from such em­pirical con­siderations, his position becomes explicitly nonpositivistic. For ex­ample, he argues against scepticism in the same way one could argue against the use of the (unverifiable) principle of verification as the basis of positivism. To assert "that there is and can be no a priori knowledge at all", chides Kant, "would be like proving by reason that there is no such thing as reason" [Kt7:12].

 

      A popular myth concerning Kant's development, which helps to breed such misconceptions about his true attitude towards metaphysics, is that he started out as a typical Wolffian rationalist, and only began formulating his "Critical" prin­ciples after being jarred by Hume out of his rationalist complacency. Yet a care­ful and open-minded reading of Kant's early (so-called "pre-Critical") works yields quite a different impression: "From the beginning he made no attempt to hide his dislike of the compact mass of Wolffian doctrine" [V2:3]; rather, his lifelong goal was to discover and follow "the correct philosophical method and by means of it to construct an eternal metaphysics" [2; see also G4:63]. A good example comes in Kt2:71(229), where Kant announces (in 1763) that he has "sought in vain from others" for an adequate philosophical method to replace "the imitation (or rather the aping) of the mathematician", which "has on the slippery ground of metaphysic occasioned a multitude of...false steps". More­over, as I have argued in P7, by 1766 (fifteen years before the publication of Kt4) Kant had already shown his awareness (in Kt3) of the crucial difference between "speculative" and "Critical" metaphysics, and of his desire to concentrate his at­tention on the latter. His philosophical "panacea", then, "was not discovered by a sudden stroke of intu­itive genius but [was] allowed slowly and painfully to reach ripe elaboration" [V2:3; see also M3 and W4].

 

      Kant expresses his true attitude towards metaphysics quite clearly in a num­ber of explicit statements throughout his writings. In Kt3:367-8(112-13), for ex­ample, he confesses:

 

Metaphysics, with which it is my fate to be in love, although only rarely can I boast of any favours from her, offers two advantages. The first is that it serves to solve the tasks which the questioning mind sets itself when by means of rea­son it inquires into the hidden qualities of things. But here the result only too often falls below expectation...

      The other advantage is more adapted to human reason, and consists in rec­ogniz­ing whether the task be within the limits of our knowledge and in stating its re­lation to the conceptions derived from experience, for these must always be the foundation of all our judgments. In so far metaphysics is the science of the boundaries of human reason. And...this use of metaphysics...is at the same time the least known and the most important, and...is obtained only late and by long experience.

 

In a letter written at about the same time (1766), Kant reveals a similar position:

 

I am far from regarding metaphysics itself, objectively considered, to be trivial or dispensable; in fact I have been convinced for some time now that I understand its nature and its proper place in human knowledge and that the true and lasting welfare of the human race depends on it... [K1:10.67(Z1:55)].

 

The significance of this early stage in Kant's development, and the nature and ex­tent of the influences of Hume, are thoroughly discussed in P7. For our present purposes it will suffice to say that Kant did not see the first Critique as a denial of his love of metaphysics, but as its truest and most secure foundation. For in a letter written just after its publication in 1781 he explains that this book "includes the meta­physics of metaphysics."[4]

 

      Such claims suggest quite clearly that Kant saw his contribution to meta­physics in terms of neither positivistic empiricism nor "pure rationalism";[5] instead, he sees himself as offering—to borrow one of his own favourite expres­sions—"a third thing". The label most often used to denote Kant's synthesis between empiricism and rationalism is the easily misunderstood title, "transcen­dental idealism". But this phrase properly refers to just one aspect of his philosophy. A more general and inclusive title would be to call it a "System of Perspectives". Interpreting Kant's philosophy in terms of the "principle of per­spective" enables us to account for the potentially confusing recurrence of both empiricist and rationalist (as well as other) elements in his philosophy.[6]

 

      If Kant was neither a straightforward positivist nor a traditional rationalist, the question yet remains how he intended his philosophy to relate to theology. As far as methodology and terminology are concerned, Barth is largely correct to say Kant "was purely a philosopher and his philosophy is not in the least dressed in the garb of theology" [B1:339]. Indeed, as Sykes points out, Kant wrote an entire essay [Part I of Kt11] "the whole object of [which] is to demonstrate the necessity of an institutionalized rivalry between theology and philosophy..." [S3:100]. But "theology" in these instances refers for Kant only to what is more accurately called "biblical studies" or "revealed theology", a discipline which Kant himself, even in his book on religion, never practised [see Kt10:8-11(7-10)]. Once the meaning of the word is widened to include any serious, scholarly study of God, religion and related subjects, his philosophy can be seen in many respects to be "theocentric" in orientation. By "theocentric" I do not mean that Kant adopted the view that our knowledge of God must serve as the basis of or centre for all other types of knowledge. On the contrary, I mean that the prob­lems surrounding our understanding of the nature and reality of God served as the driving force of his philosophy (see below).

 

      Prior to Kant most philosophers used theology—and in particular the impli­cations of God's existence (which many believed they had proved)—to bridge gaps they were unable to bridge by philosophical means alone. Two obvious exam­ples are Descartes' assumption that God's existence guarantees that "regarding ob­jects which are clearly and distinctly represented to it by the understanding, I can never be deceived" [D1:4.119], and Berkeley's theory that objects which are not being perceived by any subject can be said to persist only because they are being perceived by God. Kant, however, severely criticizes such an approach:

 

To have recourse to God...in explaining the arrangements of nature and their changes is...a complete confession that one has come to the end of his philoso­phy, since he is compelled to assume something of which in itself he otherwise has no concept in order to conceive of the possibility of something he sees before his very eyes. [Kt7:138]

 

This removal of God from his traditional place in the "gaps" of philosophical in­quiry is commonly interpreted as an example of Kant's positivistic and antitheo­logical disposition. What is often ignored by such interpreters is that, as I argue elsewhere [see P1 and P3:126-134], Kant replaces this traditional assumption with that of his famous, or infamous, concept of the "thing in itself". He has a number of reasons for doing so, among which are the preservation of the integrity of philosophy and the protection of theology from its sceptical and agnostic critics.[7] For he regards the thing in itself as the unknowable question mark of philosophical inquiry [see P2]; God is freed to play a far more important and determinant role. There is a sense in which God transcends even the thing in itself, and so, for Kant, is radically unknowable. But there is another sense in which God is immanent; indeed, this rich concept of "a living God" [Kt4:661] forms the very heart of Kant's entire philosophical project. (In other words, as I argue in P8, a real (though mysterious) God—not just an "idea" of reason—is the central focus towards which Kant's entire System points.) The interplay between these two aspects of his concept of God constitutes a valuable contribution to theology, for which he has rarely, if ever, been given full credit.

 

      Although it is true that Kant always spoke primarily as a philosopher, it is also true that "the Critical philosophy left his basic beliefs untouched" [W4:143] and that the three "ideas" which guided his entire philosophical endeavour, viz., "God, freedom, and immortality" [e.g., Kt4:xxx; Kt7:3-4; Kt8:473], are all pri­marily theocentric in their orientation. Thus it should come as no sur­prise that the concept of God "was constantly recurring throughout the various stages of [Kant's] intellectual development" [H4:13]. The inordinate attention interpreters usually give to the arguments in the Transcendental Analytic of the first Critique ironically veils the fact that Kant intends Kt4 "to clear the way for a positive account of what he regards as the correct theology for human beings" [A1:310]. Even Heine, who views Kt4 as "the sword that slew deism in Germany" [H3:107], agrees that Kant's criticism of the traditional proofs for the exis­tence of God "forms one of the main points of [Kt4]" [H3:115], and that we ought to "recognise everywhere visible in [Kt4] his polemic against these proofs" [116]. Unfortunately, he believes Kant was trying to prove that "this ideal...being, hitherto called God, is a mere fiction" [115]—a view which is thoroughly refuted in P10.

 

      Wood is one of the few interpreters to acknowledge and develop the con­structive, theocentric tenor of Kant's philosophy [see note 7]. He says in W6:17:

 

Kant is fundamentally unable to conceive of the human situation except theisti­cally... For Kant's real aim is not to destroy theology, but to replace a dogmatic theology with a Critical one: to transform rational theology from a complacent speculative science into a critical examination of the inevitable but perpetually insoluble problems of human reason, and a vehicle for the expression of our moral aspirations under the guidance of an autonomous reason.

 

He claims, quite rightly, that "there is widespread misunderstand­ing of Kant's ideas" concerning his criticism of the proofs for God's existence [10]. Moreover, Kant's Lectures on Philosophical Theology [Kt5] show, according to Wood, "that [even] the tradi­tional theology was to a large extent compatible with Kant's critical philosophy" [W6:149]. Indeed, Kant's concern for and influence on the­ology extended to numerous empirical details: not only does Barth credit him with having "understood what the idea of a Church was" and as having also "understood what grace was" [B1:339], but Sykes regards him "as one of those who prepared the way for the fragile advances of the Second Vatican Council" [S3:103]—three theological accomplishments of no small merit!

 

      Kant himself leaves no doubt as to the theocentric orientation in his under­standing of metaphysics. In 1763 he writes that "the most important of all our cognitions" is "THERE IS A GOD", and that it is so important that it is in no danger of being refuted by metaphysical speculation [Kt2:65(219)]. In 1770 he wrote to his friend Lambert, explaining that the purpose for fixing the principles and limits of knowledge is "so that these principles could not be confusedly ap­plied to objects of pure reason" [K1:10.94(Z1:59)]. That these "objects" are the ideas of God, freedom and immortality is repeatedly stressed by Kant: "Meta­physics has as the proper object of its enquiries three ideas only: God, free­dom, and immortality" [Kt4:395n]; "metaphysics has engaged so many heads up till now and will continue to engage them not in order to extend natural knowl­edge ..., but in order to attain to a knowledge of what lies entirely beyond all the boundaries of experience, namely, God, freedom, and immortality" [Kt6:477]. And in Kt9:292 he emphasizes the theocentric orientation of all metaphysics even more explicitly: "The supersensible in the world (the spiritual nature of the soul) and out of the world (God), hence immortality and theology, are the ulti­mate ends towards which metaphysics is directed."

 

      Kant also makes it clear in numerous places that his own task is ultimately constructive with respect to theology and religion, just as it is for metaphysics in general. His famous claim "to deny knowledge, in order to make room for faith" [Kt4:xxx] certainly implies something of this sort [but see also P1:442-444], especially when it is seen in context. For a large portion of the second edi­tion Preface to Kt4 is devoted to clarifying that "all objections to morality and religion" have been "for ever silenced" by this critique of reason's powers.[8] Elsewhere in Kt4 he explains that theology, morals and religion, which corre­spond to these three ideas, respectively, are "the highest ends of our existence" [395n; see also 494,656]. And in the last few pages of the Critique he concludes that, "although metaphysics cannot be the foundation of religion, it must always continue to be a bulwark of it", and that a Critical metaphysics "prevents the devastations of [speculation]...in the field of morals as well as in that of reli­gion" [877]. In the Critique of Practical Reason [Kt7] he therefore continues his task of preventing "the possibility of making theology merely a magic lantern of phantoms" [141]. Even at the end of his life, in Kt12:22.63 Kant reminds us of the theocentric orientation of his philosophy: "The highest level of the tran­scen­dental philosophy...lies in this twofold task: 1. What is God? 2. Is there a God?" [as quoted in S2:117]. Moreover, if Kant's own testimony is not evidence enough, "his friend and biographer, Jachmann" informs us, as Greene notes, "that, in private conversations with his friends ‘the philosopher and the man spoke out in undeniable testimony to an inner feeling and a genuine conviction [of God's existence]'; and that ‘in the true sense of the word he was a worshipper of God.'"[9]

 

      Copleston argues against the common trend in both theology and philoso­phy according to which philosophers such as Heidegger and theologians such as Barth stand willingly back to back, facing op­posite directions. He urges "that an adequate understanding of the Christian faith requires philosophical reflection, and that it is not facilitated by a wholesale rejection of metaphysics" [C3:53]. Taking into account the theocentric orientation of Kant's philoso­phy may help to reverse this trend, which is traceable in both dis­ciplines to various misinter­pretations of Kant. The theologian and the philosopher might then be more will­ing to stand face to face; for Kant destroyed the old parent-child relationship of theology to philosophy not in order to make them complete strangers, but rather to enable them to work side by side towards a common goal. "The ulti­mate aim" of such cooperation, Smith suggests, is "to overcome the emptiness and formal­ity of philosophy and to frustrate the obscurantist and parochial ten­dencies in theology" [S1:8].

 

      Learning to read Kant's philosophy always in the light of its theological and religious implications can be particularly helpful in fulfilling this task because he is respected almost universally by philosophers as one of the great philosoph­ical thinkers in the history of Western philosophy—if not the greatest. Indeed, many would agree that "Kant, in modern times, has replaced Aristotle as a kind of intellectual reference system" [G1:135]. Likewise, the number of theologians and philosophers of religion who acknowledge Kant's achievement is so large as to render it hopeless even to attempt to draw up an exhaustive list. Many the­ologians would agree with MacKinnon's view that Kant is "surely the supreme German philosopher" [M1:135; see also M2:22-6 and L1:16]. Even Gilson, who has fundamental disagreements with Kant, regards him as the primary philosoph­ical alternative to Thomas Aquinas for the Christian [G2:114]. What Barth says of Kant's influence on nineteenth-century theologians would apply to most (non-Barthian) theologians in the twentieth century as well: "He stands by himself...a stumbling-block and rock of offence..., someone determinately pursuing his own course, more feared than loved, a prophet whom almost everyone even among those who wanted to go forward with him had first to re-interpret before they could do anything with him" [B1:267].

 

      If indeed Kant is the primary figure in the modern Western philosophical tradition, the theologian can hardly ignore him. For, as Wood suggests: "To face up squarely to the problems of the tradition, as Kant did, remains by far the most straightforward and intellectually honest way for a modern theologian to dis­charge his philosophical responsibilities" [W6:151]. To interpret Kant in a way that is philosophically acceptable and yet leaves open a legitimate field in which the theologian can work [see e.g., Part Four of P11] would therefore effec­tively establish much-needed common ground between philosophy and theology.

 

      But the respect Kant evokes from philosophers and theologians is not the only reason for recommending a theologically-conscious way of reading this over-worked philosopher. An even more important reason stems from a problem we acknowledged near the beginning of this article. Kant is far too frequently in­terpreted in a one-sided fashion, especially by those who (conveniently) claim that large portions of his work are irrelevant to or inconsistent with the "truly Kantian" material. Because of the confusion this creates, especially for anyone whose primary concern is not philosophical, many theologians and philosophers of religion have ignored or repudiated the importance of Kant. A typical exam­ple is Flew's book on the philosophy of religion [F3], which entirely ignores the relevance of Kant's views on the subject: he devotes only two paragraphs [5.44-5] to a brief description and trite criticism. Rather than merely listing other works which make such a mistake, let us examine one case in slightly more de­tail.

 

      Hartshorne's treatment of Kant is even more misleading than Flew's, because he gives the impression of being more knowledge­able. With Reese he voices the common objection: "Of all criticisms of philosophical theology, probably none has been so influential as those of Kant.... [However,] Kant's criticisms depend, more than is commonly noted, on certain features of his own system which are now usually rejected" [H2:142]. They then severely misinter­pret and trivialize, among other things, Kant's doctrine of sensibility [147]. As evidence of their failure to grasp the essential thrust of Kant's philosophy, they accuse him of being "imprisoned in the half-truths in which the monopolar prej­udice, the neglect of the principle of polarity, is bound to result" [146]. Each of these criticisms, however, and especially the latter, betrays an acceptance of an overly simplified or one-sided interpretation of Kant—an interpretation of the type which assumes that theologians who accept Kant must give up most or all of their endeavours. The implications of such a second-hand approach are brought out more clearly in Hartshorne's defense of the ontological argument [H1], which is itself based on a neglect of Kant's principle of perspective. Describing Kant as a "calamitously overestimated German philosopher" [221], Hartshorne explic­itly rejects Kant's Copernican revolution [232], and evinces his neglect of Kan­tian methodology in general when he boldly states: "Unbelief [in God] is confu­sion or else belief is confusion. There is no third possibility" [135; but see P1]. Such philosophers of religion and theologians remain unaware of—or at least, un­receptive towards—the true contribution Kant has made to their subject. This alone, if nothing else, calls for a fresh reminder of just what that contribu­tion is, so that the doors of theological reflection can remain open even (or espe­cially) for the Kantian—and, indeed, vice versa.

 

      Our tentative answer to the question with which we began, therefore, is that Kant destroyed not so much the possibility of theology as that of the one-sided rationalist spirit of the Enlightenment, under which he himself had been nur­tured. His genius, however, was to have done this without going to the oppo­site ex­treme of positivism. In the process of working out his new approach, he pro­posed numerous theories which are highly relevant to the theologian. (I have discussed some of these in P1 and P6-P10.) But because his theological interests are so deeply imbedded within his philosophy, and because the commonly ac­cepted in­ter­pretations ignore this and other important emphases, such as the de­pendence of his arguments on the principle of perspective, it would be necessary to rein­ter­pret his entire Critical System in the light of such issues [see P11] be­fore bring­ing into full view all the details arising out of its thoroughly theocen­tric orienta­tion.

 

 

Bibliography

 

I. Works by Kant (abbreviated "Kt")

 

Kt1:     Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels oder Versuch von der Ver­fassung und dem mechanischen Ursprunge des ganzen Weltgebäudes, nach New­tonischen Grundsätzen abgehandelt, 1755, in K1:1.215-368. Tr. S.L. Jaki as Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens (Edinburgh: Scottish Aca­demic Press, 1981).

Kt2:     Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes, 1763, K1:2.63-163. Tr. anonymously (by J. Richardson) as The Only Possible Argument for the Demonstra­tion of the Existence of God in his Essays and Treatises on Moral, Political, Religious and Various Philosophical Subjects, vol. 1 (London: William Richardson, 1798), pp.217-366.

Kt3:     Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik, 1766, K1:2.315-73. Tr. E. Goerwitz as Dreams of a Spirit Seer Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics, ed. F. Sewal (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1900).

Kt4:     Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 1787, K1:3.passim; also 1781, K1:4.1-252. Tr. N. Kemp Smith as Critique of Pure Reason (London: Macmillan, 1929). References are to the pagination of the second German edition.

Kt5:     Vorlesungen über die philosophische Religionslehre, based on lectures de­liv­ered in approximately 1783-4 (ed. K. Beyer, 1937), K1:vol. 28.2,2. Tr. A.W. Wood and G.M. Clark as Lectures on Philosophical Theology (London: Cornell Univ. Press, 1978). Translation does not follow the order of the K1 text.

Kt6:     Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft, 1786, K1:4.465-565. Tr. J. Ellington as Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970).

Kt7:     Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, 1788, K1:5.1-163. Tr. L.W. Beck as Cri­tique of Practical Reason (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956).

Kt8:     Kritik der Urteilskraft, 1790, K1:5.165-485. Tr. J.C. Meredith as Kant's Cri­tique of Judgement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952).

Kt9:     Welches sind die wirklichen Fortschritte, die die Metaphysik seit Leib­nitzens und Wolf's Zeiten in Deutschland gemacht hat?, 1791 (ed. F.T. Rink, 1804), K1:20.253-311. Tr. T.B. Humphrey as Progress in Metaphysics (New York: Abaris, 1983).

Kt10:Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft, 1793, K1:6.1-202. Tr. T.M. Greene and H.H. Hudson as Religion Within the Limits of Rea­son Alone (New York: Harper & Row, 1960).

Kt11:Der Streit der Facultäten, 1798, K1:7.1-116. Tr. M.J. Gregor as The Con­flict of the Faculties (New York: Abaris, 1979).

Kt12:Opus Postumum, notes written mostly between 1796 and 1803, K1:21-22.passim. German edition edited by E. Adickes, Kants Opus Postumum (Berlin: Reuther & Reichard, 1920).

 

II. Other Sources

 

A1: Axelsen, Diana E., "Kant's Metaphor For Persons and Community", Philos­ophy & Theology III.4 (Summer 1989), pp.301-321.

B1: Barth, Karl, Die Protestantische Theologie im 19. Jahrhundert, 1952. Tr. B. Cozens and J. Bowden as Protestant Theology in the Nineteenth Century (London: SCM, 1972).

C1: Collins, James, God in Modern Philosophy (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1960).

C2: -----, The Emergence of Philosophy of Religion (New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1967).

C3: Copleston, Frederick C., Religion and Philosophy (Dublin: Gill and Macmil­lan, 1974).

C4: Cupitt, Don, "Kant and the Negative Theology", B. Hebblethwaite and S. Sutherland (eds.), The Philosophical Frontiers of Christian Theology (London: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1982), pp.55-67.

D1: Descartes, Rene, Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting the Rea­son. Tr. E.S. Haldane and G.R.T. Ross in The Philosophical Works of Descartes (London: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1970). Reference is to section and page number.

D2: Despland, Michel, Kant on History and Religion (Montreal: McGill-Queen's Univ. Press, 1973).

E1: England, F.E., Kant's Conception of God (London: Allen & Unwin, 1929).

F1: Findlay, J.N., "Kant Today", P. Laberge, et. al. (eds.), Proceedings of the Ot­tawa Congress on Kant in the Anglo-American and Continental Traditions Held October 10-14, 1974 (Ottawa: Universtiy of Ottawa Press, 1976), pp.3-16.

F2: Findlay, J.N., Kant and the Transcendental Object (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981).

F3: Flew, Antony, God & Philosophy (London: Hutchinson, 1966). Reference is to chapter and paragraph numbers.

G1: Genova, A.C., "Kant's Three Critiques: A Suggested Analytical Frame­work", Kant-Studien 60 (1969), pp. 135-46.

G2: Gilson, ütienne, God and Philosophy (New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1941).

G3: -----, The Unity of Philosophical Experience (New York: Scrib­ner's, 1950).

G4: Goldmann, Lucien, Introduction á la philosophie de Kant, 1967. Tr. R. Black as Immanuel Kant (London: NLB, 1971).

G5: Greene, Theodore M., "The Historical Context and Religious Significance of Kant's Religion", in his translation of Kt10, pp.ix-lxxviii.

H1: Hartshorne, Charles, Anselm's Discovery: A Re-Examination of the Onto­logi­cal Proof for God's Existence (Lasalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1965).

H2: Hartshorne, Charles and Reese, William L., Philosophers Speak of God (London: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1953).

H3: Heine, Heinrich, Zur Geschichte der Religion und Philosophie in Deutschland2, 1852 (1834). Tr. J. Snodgrass as Religion and Philosophy in Germany (Boston: Beacon Press, 1959 [1882]).

H4: Hicks, G. Dawes, "Forward" in E1:13-8.

K1:     Kants gesammelte schriften, Preukilchen Akademie der Wissen­schaften (eds.), 29 vols. (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1902-). References are to volume and page number(s).

K2:     Kemp Smith, Norman, A Commentary to Kant's "Critique of Pure Rea­son"2 (London: Macmillan, 1923 [1918]).

K3:      Kuehn, Manfred, "Kant's Transcendental Deduction of God's Existence as a Pos­tulate of Pure Practical Reason", Kant-Studien 76.2 (1985), pp.152-169.

L1: Lewis, H.D., Philosophy of Religion (London: English Universities Press, 1965).

M1:      MacKinnon, Donald M., Explorations in Theology 5 (London: SCM, 1979).

M2:   -----, Borderlands of Theology and Other Essays (London: Lutterworth, 1968).

M3:      Martin, Gottfried, Immanuel Kant, Ontologie und Wissenschaftstheorie, 1951. Tr. P.G. Lucas as Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science (Manchester: Manchester Univ. Press, 1955).

O1:      Oman, John, The Problem of Faith and Freedom in the Last Two Centuries (London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1906).

P1: Palmquist, Stephen, "Faith as Kant's Key to the Justification of Transcen­dental Reflection", The Heythrop Journal 25.4 (October 1984), pp. 442-55.

P2: -----, "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's ‘Thing in Itself'", Cogito III.2 (March 1985), pp. 101-115.

P3: -----, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", Di­alec­tica 40.2 (l986), pp. 121-51.

P4: -----, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", Metaphiloso­phy 17.4 (October 1986), pp. 266-88.

P5: -----, "Knowledge and Experience—An Examination of the Four Reflective ‘Per­spec­tives' in Kant's Critical Philosophy", Kant-Studien 78 (1987), pp.170-200.

P6: -----, "Immanuel Kant: A Christian Philosopher?", Faith and Philosophy 6.1 (January 1989), pp.65-75.

P7: -----, "Kant's Critique of Mysticism: (1) The Critical Dreams", Philosophy & Theology 3.4 (Summer 1989), pp.355-383.

P8: -----, "Kant's Critique of Mysticism: (2) Critical Mysticism", Philosophy & Theology 4.1 (Fall 1989), pp.67-94.

P9: -----, "Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality?", Kant-Studien 83 (1992), in press.

P10:        -----, "Kant's Theistic Solution to the Problem of Transcendental Theology", Rodica Croitoru (ed.), Kant and the Transcendental Problem (Bucharest:  Uni­v. of Bucharest Faculty of Philoso­phy, 1991), pp.148-178. Thoroughly revised as "Kant's ‘Appropriation' of Lampe's God", Harvard Theological Review 85.1 (January 1992), in press.

P11:  -----, Kant's System of Perspectives (Washington D.C.: Univ. Press of America, in press).

R1: Rabel, Gabriele (ed.), Kant (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963).

S1: Smith, John E., Experience and God (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1968).

S2: Sullivan, William J., "Kant on the Existence of God in the Opus Postu­mum", The Modern Schoolman 48.2 (January 1971), pp. 117-33.

S3: Sykes, S.W., "Theological Study: The Nineteenth Century and After", B. Hebblethwaite and S. Sutherland (eds.), The Philosophical Frontiers of Chris­tian Theology (London: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1982), pp.95-118.

V1: Vaihinger, Hans, Commentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 2 vols. (Stuttgart: Verlag von W. Spemann, 1881 and 1892).

V2: Vleeschauwer, Herman-J. de, L'Evolution de la pensèe Kantienne, 1939. Tr. A.R.C. Duncan as The Development of Kantian Thought (London: Nel­son, 1962).

W1:      Walsh, W.H., "Kant's Moral Theology", Proceedings of the British Academy 49 (1963), pp.261-289.

W2:      -----, Metaphysics (London: Hutchinson Univ. Library, 1963).

W3:      -----, Kant's Criticism of Metaphysics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh Univ. Press, 1975).

W4:      Ward, Keith, The Development of Kant's View of Ethics (Oxford: Basil Black­well, 1972).

W5:      Wood, Allen W., Kant's Moral Religion (London: Cornell Univ. Press, 1970).

W6:      -----, Kant's Rational Theology (London: Cornell Univ. Press, 1978).

Z1: Zweig, Arnulf (tr. & ed.), Kant: Philosophical Correspondence 1759-99 (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1967).

 

 

 

This etext is based on a prepublication draft of the published version of this essay.

 

Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

 

My Web Counter identifies you as visitor number

  

 

to this page, last updated on 4 April 2011. Please come again!

 

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published articles.

 

Back to the main map of Steve Palmquist's web site.

 

 



[1]. References which do not require further comment are included in the main text, as here. The letter-number abbreviation refers to the corresponding book listed in the Bibliography. After the colon, the relevant page number(s) of that work is given, unless otherwise specified in the bibliographical entry. All references to Kant's writings refer to the Academy edition (= K1); this is followed by the English pagina­tion (in brackets) for translations which do not provide the German pagination.

 

[2]. G3:310. This view was popularised in Germany by Vaihinger [V1], and in Britain by Kemp Smith [K2], both of whom "take a Kantian doctrine to be ‘critical' in pro­por­tion as it involves a rejection of the metaphysics of Kant's rationalist predeces­sors" [W6:59].

 

[3]. In K3 Kuehn offers a thorough critique of the position supported by Ward in W4, by Wood in W5 and W6 and by Walsh in W1 and W3:229-241, all of whom "consider Kant's ‘moral arguments' as ‘an integral part of the critical philosophy'" [K3:155, quoting W5:9]. Kuehn claims "it is highly misleading to say that Kant wanted to jus­tify a ‘personal' faith" [K3:168]. His main worry is that by "interpreting Kant's rational faith as a personal commitment..., they turn Kant's enterprise, which con­sisted in showing the rationality of religious faith, upside down" [K3:169]. However, nei­ther of these extremes on its own does justice to Kant's intentions, which were in­deed to justify a kind of personal faith, but to do so not by appealing to its existential baselessness, but by demonstrating how it is based on "impersonal" (i.e., objective, ahistorical) grounds.

 

[4]. K1:10.252(Z1:95). This claim does not contradict Kant's assertion in a later letter (1783) that Kt4 "is not at all metaphysics..., but a whole new science..., the critique of an a priori judging reason" [10.318(102)]. The latter can be regarded as Kant's ex­planation of what the phrase "metaphysics of metaphysics" actually means. In Kt9:316 Kant explains that metaphysics proper is "the science of proceeding from knowledge of the sensible to that of the supersensible." The same order is, in fact, adopted in Kt4, from the Aesthetic to the Dialectic; the difference is that the Dialectic concludes not with knowledge of the supersensible, but with an explanation of why such knowledge is impossible.

 

[5]. See e.g., O1:188 and B1:345. Barth notes that for Kant such "rationalism" refers only to "practical reason" [281]. But even taken in its practical sense such a label is misleading, since it highlights only one aspect of Kant's philosophy.

 

[6]. I have developed this new way of interpreting Kant in various articles [see espe­cially P3, P4 and P5]. P11 is a thoroughgoing application of the principle of per­spective to Kant's entire philosophical System, with a view towards demonstrating its radically metaphysical (and so also, theological) orientation.

 

[7]. The almost universally accepted caricature of Kant is as an agnostic deist, con­cerned only with a rather fanciful concept of God as nothing but a "regulative idea of reason", a concept which is criticized as being dry, theologically uninteresting (or even repugnant) and scientifically untenable. Several recent scholars, most notably Wood, Collins and Despland, have done much to dispel this misconception. Wood, for instance, interprets Kant's theology as "rich, precise, philosophically sophisti­cated" [W6:151; see also W5:164]. And Despland asserts that "Kant's doctrine of God ...is the most important part of his doctrinal metaphysics" [D2:135]. Although in C2 Collins repudiates his own previous assessment of Kant's theology as entirely de­structive [see e.g., C1:183], even in C1 he had suggested that Kant's "preoccupa­tion with the problem of God" [166] results in the fact that "his stand on God partly determined his philosophical position at any given stage" in his development [162]. By placing Kant's theology in its proper philosophical context I have attempted in P7-P10 to further this recent trend by eradicating the above-mentioned mistake once and for all.

        Such an emphasis on the centrality of this "idea of reason" (i.e., God) might ap­pear to contradict a remark Kant makes in a famous letter to Garve (1798): "It was not the investigation of the existence of God, immortality, and so on, but rather the anti­nomy of pure reason...that...first aroused me from my dogmatic slum­ber and drove me to the critique of reason itself, in order to resolve the scandal of ostensible contradic­tion of reason with itself" [K1:12.255(Z1:99n)]. If we remember, however, that Kant is here making an assertion about his own histor­ical development, not about the essential nature of metaphysics or of his own phi­losophy, then the discrepancy dis­appears. The antinomies may have been the his­tor­ical occasion for Kant conceiving of the idea of a critique of reason, but when he fi­nally carried it out, he did so by directing the focus of the System itself to the task of understanding the proper place of the three (theologically oriented) ideas of reason. It is perhaps relevant to note here that in a much earlier letter to Garve (1783) Kant ex­plains that the solution to the problem of the antinomies "consists in this: that all objects that are given to us can be interpreted in two ways: on the one hand, as ap­pearances; on the other hand, as things in themselves" [K1:10.320n(Z1:103n)]. In other words, the key he dis­covered entailed the proper implementation of what I refer to as Kant's "principle of perspective" [see note 6].

 

[8]. Kt4:xxxi; see also 781-2. Kant made a similar remark to Herz as early as 1773, when he confided: "I reveal to no one but you: the hope that by means of this work philosophy will be given a durable form, a different and—for religion and morality—more favorable turn" [K1:10.137(Z1:78); see also E1:79]. Earlier still, in the preface to Kt1, Kant reveals the importance he placed on the consistency of his own ideas with religion when he stresses his confidence in the "harmony...between my system [of cosmogony] and religion" [222(82)].

 

[9]. G5:lxxvii-lxxviii (Greene's brackets). Thus Copleston's description of "transcen­dent metaphysics" as "the exposition of a religious quest" [C3:9] applies equally well to Kant's non-transcendent, Critical metaphysics. For as Rabel points out in R1:vii, and as I argue in detail in P8, "Kant was a profoundly religious man." This view of Kant is supported in A1:312: "Kant always saw his philosophical task as fostering faith, not merely as identifying the demands of duty."

 

 

 

 

 

 

---

 

This etext is based on a prepublication draft of the published version of this essay.

 

Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

 

My Web Counter identifies you as visitor number

 

For the page of published articles (and all the articles linked thereto), use:

 

 

to this page, last updated on 1 June 2001. Please come again!

 

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published articles.