How is "Christian Tradition" Logically Possible?

 

Prof. Stephen Palmquist, D.Phil. (Oxon)

Department of Religion and Philosophy

Hong Kong Baptist University

(stevepq@hkbu.edu.hk)

 

Then some Pharisees and scribes came to Jesus from Jerusalem, saying, "Why do your disciples transgress the tradition of the elders?"  ....  And he answered and said to them, "And why do you yourselves transgress the commandment of God for the sake of your tradition?"  [Matthew 15:1-3]

 

1. The Paradox

            A philosophical account of the logical possibility of "Christian tradition" can hardly begin without some basic understanding of what is meant by the terms "Christian" and "tradition".  If our interest[1] were in the historical possibility of Christian traditions, we could simply point to some group of people who call themselves "Christian" and who have existed over a period of time, and say "See, there it is; Christian tradition must be possible!"  But when our interest is philosophical, the matter is not so simple.  For, as we shall see, a paradox lies at the very basis of our question--a paradox which must be resolved before we can clearly identify what a tradition would look like if it were truly Christian.

            In this paper I will regard a "tradition" as a set of guidelines for living which is accepted by a community of like-minded persons and which persists over a span of time exceeding one generation.[2]  The set of guidelines in a religious tradition will include not only theoretical beliefs (such as dogmas) and practical actions (such as moral rules and regulations), but also empirical or existential patterns of behavior (such as rites and rituals).  An important feature of the guidelines which compose a tradition is that they are, in varying degrees, self-serving.  That is, they exist, in part at least, for the sake of their own (and thus, the tradition's) self-preservation.  This holds true not only for religious traditions, but also for philosophical schools of thought, which are typically estab­lished on the basis of one person's dynamic and courageous breakthrough into new areas, but which before long turn into "traditions" which are themselves eventually over­thrown by just such breakthroughs.  (Consider, for example, the differences between Plato and Platonism, Kant and Kantianism, etc.)  And indeed, much the same could be said for anything calling itself a tradition, whether it be the tradi­tion of a family, a society, a club, or anything else. Its function as a tradition is to preserve the institution against the threat of nonbeing.

            In this sense, the "Christian tradition" as we normally think of it began as the first generation of believers were dying off and the re­maining Christians felt the need to preserve their movement against the threat of nonbeing.  One of the most important steps in this direction was to write accounts of Jesus' life, death and resurrection, and of the early church, in a form which could be passed on after the eyewitnesses were gone.  (Of course, there were also many other factors leading the writers to compose the books of the New Testament.)  Before the books of the New Testament were written, there was, to be sure, a so-called "oral tradition"; but in a significant sense (as we shall see) it was not self-serving.  The first generation of believers did not need such a fixed tradition precisely because of their belief in the immanent return of Jesus.  The more that hope died away, or was significantly revised, the more important it was for them to fix some tradition to insure the propagation of the gospel.

            Making Christianity into a tradition seems legitimate, since this would appear to be the only way in which Christians can fulfill the Great Commission [see Matt. 28:19-20].  Yet how can this be reconciled with the notion, held by many Christians (including those in the early church), that Christianity is first and foremost a religion of the cross?  When the Christian gospel incites its adherents to die to the world [Matt. 10:39; 16:25; cf. Rom. 8:13], to take up their cross and follow Jesus [Matt. 10:38; 16:24], does this not include dying to the all-too-human temptation towards self-preservation?  As Paul puts it so succinctly, "For to me, to live is Christ, and to die is gain" [Phil. 1:21].  Although the cross is surely the central symbol of Christianity, Christians too often accept only its application to human individuals, and fail to appreciate its broader application, according to which it requires all human traditions and institutions to die. The latter notion suggests that Christianity is not to become yet another tradition among traditions, but is to serve in some way as a force for relativizing all mere traditions, so that "God may be all in all" [1 Cor. 15:28].

            If we take seriously this necessary connection between "being a Christian" and "dying to self", we are now faced with a logical problem as to how any Christian "tradition" could be possible.  The paradox arises as soon as we realize that the Christian Church, as the "body of Christ" [1 Cor. 12:12,27] is itself meant to "die to self", just as is each individual Christian.  Yet if the church were to die, how would the Great Commission be fulfilled?  The task of this paper will be to find a solution to, or at least a way of coping with, this logical conundrum, which can be precisely stated as follows:  How can a person whose life is centered around a symbol of self-denial (i.e., around the "self-giving love" of the cross) depend on a time-honored set of human guidelines, enshrined as valid in themselves?  Or, put in more general terms:  How can a tradition be Christian?

 


2. The Christian Tradition in Perspective

            To some extent we are faced here with nothing other than the familiar problem of self-reference.  If, for example, I say "all the statements made in this paper are false", then my statement can make sense only if this one statement is exempted from the set of "false statements in this paper".  The problem we are now facing is of the same form:  if I say "my tradition requires me to deny the ultimate validity of all traditions", then it would seem that the tradition expressed by this one statement must be exempted from the set of "traditions which must be ultimately denied".  But does this make sense?  What could it mean to call such a notion a "tradition"?  Would it be better simply to find another word and resolve the paradox by saying there is no possibility of having a truly "Christian" tradition?

            If we follow the requirements of traditional ("analytic") logic, then the only consistent position would seem to be to adopt something along the lines of the "way of negation", described so forcefully in the fifth century by Pseudo-Dionysius.  In his attempt to discover something literally true about the "It" which holds the world together, which we might call the "ultimate reality", he found that logic leaves us empty handed, as long as we are unwilling to affirm a paradox:

Once more, ascending yet higher we maintain that It is not soul or mind, or endowed with the faculty of imagination, conjecture, reason, or understanding; nor is It any act of reason or under­standing; nor can It be described by the reason or perceived by the understanding, since It is not number or order or greatness or littleness or equality or inequality, and since It is not immovable nor in motion or at rest and has no power and is not power or light and does not live and is not life; nor is It personal essence or eternity or time; nor can it be grasped by the understanding, since It is not knowledge or truth; nor is It kingship or wisdom; nor is It one, nor is It unity, nor is It Godhead or Goodness...; nor is It any other thing such as we or any other being can have knowledge of; nor does It belong to the category of nonexistence or to that of existence; nor do existent beings know It as it actually is, nor does It know them as they actually are; nor can the reason attain to It to name It or to know It; nor is It darkness, nor is It light or error or truth; nor can any affirmation or negation apply to It..., inasmuch as It transcends all affirmation by being the perfect and unique Cause of all things, and transcends all negation by the preeminence of Its simple and absolute nature--free from every limitation and beyond them all.[3]

This shows us, among other things, how analytic logic on its own leaves us with nothing but a list of what we might call "negative paradoxes" in our search for the ultimate ground of religion.

            By contrast, if we are willing to affirm the paradox (which is what we do any time we affirm a symbolic meaning[4]), then we find our hands are full of a good deal of meaningful statements.  But the logical form of their meaning can be understood only by recognizing their dependence on what I call "synthetic logic"--i.e., the logic of paradox.  Synthetic logic is based on a special "law of contradiction" (A=-A), which is the opposite of analytic logic's famous "law of noncontradiction" (A/-A).  In other words, synthetic logic recognizes that an intentionally self-contradictory statement may nevertheless have some significant meaning.[5]

            With this distinction between analytic and synthetic logic in mind, we can return to the question of the logical possibility of having a "Christian tradition".  In the first section of this paper I suggested, by implication at least, that any attempt to solidify the Christian message into an absolute form (whether it be through doctrine, moral rules, rituals, etc.) is by its very nature taking a step away from what it really means to be Christian.  The problem this raises is that throughout the past twenty centuries, nearly everyone associated with Christianity has in fact adhered to some set of guidelines which would fall under the foregoing description of a "tradition".  Indeed, Jesus himself, if we are to believe the gospel writers, instituted at least two basic rituals (baptism [e.g., Mark 1:8; 16:16] and communion [e.g., Luke 22:17-20]), at least two basic moral rules (love God and man [cf. Matt. 22:36-40] and "take up [your] cross, and follow me" [e.g., Matt. 16:24]), and at least two basic doctrines ("I am the way..." [John 14:6] and "the kingdom of heaven is at hand" [e.g., Matt.3:2]).  Was he not by this very fact giving birth to a new tradition?

            Before answering this question, it may be helpful to respond to a possible objection to this whole line of reasoning.  Perhaps the very assumption that Jesus intended to shatter old traditions is incorrect.  For Jesus does claim in the Sermon on the Mount that he came not to abolish the law (which was the basis for the Jewish tradition), but to fulfill it [Matt. 5:17].  The question this raises is:  Just what does it mean to "fulfill" a tradition?  I believe Jesus did not intend his comment to give the Jewish tradition a kind of rubber stamp of approval, as some Christians have assumed.  For Jesus himself on at least several occasions broke the rules which were to function as this traditional "law" [e.g., Matt. 12:1-2; 15:1-3]. Nor is he shrugging it off as merely a worthless mistake.  Rather, he is putting the tradition in its proper perspective by claiming that the Christian Way will be the way of fulfilling traditions by bringing them to their rightful end, or goal, and thereby putting an end to them.

            How is this task accomplished?  First of all, Jesus reverses the order in which human beings traditionally place themselves in relation to their tradition:  "[tradition] was made for man, and not man for [tradition]" [cf. Mark 2:27].  Secondly, he cuts his followers loose from bondage to anyone who would claim to be a "teacher", "father", or "leader" [Matt. 23:8-10; 1 John 2:27]--that is, anyone whose position in life encourages them to have a vested interest in preserving the tradition for its own sake.  But most of all, Jesus accomplishes the Christian task by dying, which for his followers means dying to the whole idea that adherence to a tradition can be the source of one's salvation.  This insight is the basis for Jesus' claim that "unless your righteousness surpasses that of the scribes and Pharisees, you shall not enter the kingdom of heaven" [Matt. 5:20].  Jesus is not telling his disciples they must follow the tradition better than those who guard the tradition; rather, he is telling them they must do more than simply follow a tradition, and proceeds to give numerous examples [see Matt. 5:21-48], which show that the way of the cross shatters the notion that a tradition as such can be "Christian".

            This means that if Jesus was indeed intending to give birth to a tradition, it was surely to be a kind of "non-traditional tradition".  In other words, it was to be a self-transcending, or even self-negating, tradition--a tradition which would break all the rules of what it means to be a tradition, so that the pain and division caused by conflicting traditions could be overcome.  And this, clearly, can be understood only in terms of synthetic logic.  Indeed, we have now reached the first significant step in answering our original question.  "Christian tradition" is logically possible only if we are willing to interpret it in terms of synthetic logic.

            Once we recognize this, all of the above-mentioned examples of traditions instituted by Jesus can be seen to be designed explicitly to avoid the temptation of turning Christianity into a typical, self-serving tradi­tion.  Baptism symbolizes a believer's choice to die to all the world's traditions in order to be raised up to the freedom of a life unfettered by traditional distinctions [see e.g., Gal. 3:28].  Communion symbolizes the church's willingness to do the same thing: to participate as a community in the broken body and shed blood of a self-denying sav­ior.  Love, Christian love that is, is the act of giving up the rights which are due a person in virtue of his or her membership in a certain tradition, and giving oneself instead to someone outside that tradition (i.e., to God, and so also, to the unlovely).[6]  The cross, as we have seen, is a rich symbol of self-denial for the sake of a higher goal.  Jesus could affirm himself as the Christ (i.e., as "the way, and the truth, and the life") because his own life, death, and resurrection fully realize the meaning of this symbol.  And the kingdom of heaven, the context for virtually all of Jesus' teaching, is itself the vision of a non-political politics, the only context in which a non-traditional religious tradition (i.e., Christianity) could flourish.[7]

 

3. The Non-Traditional Tradition

            The recognition that Christianity is in its very essence a non-traditional tradition can help us to understand why the Jewish authorities felt so threatened by Jesus' gospel.  Nothing he did or said challenged the validity of the content of their tradition.  Such challenges were never part of Jesus' proclamation, since he was neither a philosopher nor a theologian!  Rather, they were irritated by the gospel because it struck the very root of the human situation and revealed the Jewish leaders to be engaged in the age-old, self-serving game of pleasing themselves through the propagation of their tradition, rather than being engaged in serving God, as they claimed to be doing.[8]

            One lesson to be learned from this, as far as we Christian scholars are concerned, is that we must beware of assuming we are serving God when we use our intellectual acumen to support and embellish the content of the particular form of Christian tradition with which we associate ourselves.  Such service, the "analysis" of the tradition as it already stands, does, no doubt, have its proper place.  But we must be aware of the fact that we are serving the tradition, and thus serving man whenever we engage in it.  Such a noble mission will be no more Christian than the Pharisees' "mint and dill and cumin" if we "neglect the weightier provisions" [Matt. 13:23] of our vocation, which require us to break through old thought-forms and seek to establish reconcilia­tion between opposing points of view (i.e., opposing traditions).  All too often, by ignoring this "synthetic" task, we are the very ones who, just like the "blind guides" Jesus criticized so harshly, "strain out a gnat and swallow a camel!" [23:24]. 

            A good example of how it is not the content of our tradition, but our attitude towards it, which determines the extent to which we are justified in calling our tradition "Christian" can be given by comparing the Catholic and Protestant branches of what we have become accustomed to calling the "Christian tradition".  (This can also serve as a good example of how we can break through old traditions by adopting a synthetic point of view.)  The Catholic church was certainly right to think of the gospel as "universal" (from the Greek, katholou); but at an early stage it failed to recognize that the universal element lies not in a particular tradition, but in the protest against the universal validity of any tradition.  The Protestant church, of course, eventually called attention to this prob­lem. Unfortunately, because protestants generally fail to recognize that a Christian tradition requires universal protest, their tradition has divided into innumerable discrete, mostly self-perpetuating, religious traditions.  As long as the basic schism between Catholic and Protestant exists, we can hardly call either of these two traditions, as such, the "Christian" tradition, inasmuch as each tends to be self-serving to the extent that it excludes the other.  A truly Christian tradition would be a catholic protestantism and/or a protestant catholicism.

            Paul Tillich follows a similar line of reasoning in determining how creeds and confessions should be constructed in a religious tradition.  After arguing in his book, Dynamics of Faith, that doubt is a necessary element in faith, Tillich poses the problem created by the fact that a "community of faith" normally "needs creedal expressions of the concrete elements of its ultimate concern."[9]  When creeds are taken to provide "infallible statements" which allow for no doubt, as is so often assumed, they paradoxically stifle the faith they are meant to support. The only way out, Tillich claims, is "that creedal expressions of the ultimate concern of the community must include their own criticism.  It must become obvious in all of them...that they are not ultimate.  Rather, their function is to point to the ultimate which is beyond them all."[10]  He refers to this requirement as the "Protestant principle", and adds:  "Criticism and doubt show that the community of faith stands 'under the cross'...".[11]

            Tillich makes a similar point in an early essay on "The Basic Principles of Religious Socialism".[12]  At one point he explains that "the exclusiveness of confessionalism" can best be avoided

not by criticism of confessionalism in general, but, rather, by a deepening of the confession to the point where it negates itself before the Unconditional....  The more it negates itself from the point of view of the Unconditional, the more justified [is] a claim to absoluteness by a confession or a church...[13]

And the same is true, we might add, for a tradition, or any aspect of a tradition.  Indeed, as Tillich rightly says:  "Religion is truer the more it cancels itself out as religion..."[14]

            A good example of how the creedal core of a religious tradition can be "self-negating" is found in the Ten Commandments.  For the first commandment, properly understood, negates the absolute validity of the other nine by requiring that nothing, not even the other nine command­ments, must come before God in one's life.  Keeping this in mind, we can surmise that when Moses breaks the original tablets (after seeing God's people worshipping an idol [cf. Ex. 32:1-9 and Deut. 9:17]), he may be expressing more than just his anger at the people's impatience and obstinacy.  For if this were the only problem, he would have reacted not by breaking the tablets but by hurrying to enforce them as the proper object of worship.  Instead, his reaction may also have resulted from his realization that even these words from God were destined to be worshipped in God's place.  If so, the fact that God does not punish Moses for breaking the tablets, but invites him back to receive a second set [Deut. 10:1-5] can be regarded as a symbol of the resurrection which follows the cross.  In this case, it would suggest that the only proper attitude towards any such creed or confession is to regard it as having a broken character (as opposed to one which is "absolute").  My use of synthetic logic in this paper is intended to provide a guideline for how words can be used in such a way as to accomplish just such a task.

            One way to insure that a non-traditional tradition will be self-negating towards its particular contents will be to base it not on a creed (or any other fixed content, such as a scripture), but upon a person.  The New Testament itself clearly supports this way of under­standing the Christian tradition, not only by its ubiquitous emphasis on Christ as the beginning, the end, and the focus of all aspects of Christianity [see e.g., John 1:1; Gal. 2:20; Rev. 22:13], but also by its description of the proper attitude towards more peripheral aspects of one's Christian tradition, such as scriptures.  This point could hardly be made more forcefully than it is in John 5:39, where Jesus first criticizes those who "search the Scriptures, because you think that in them you have eternal life"--that is, those who regard the scriptures as the source of an absolute, self-serving tradition.  But he then immediately explains that their mistake is in the failure to see that "it is these [scriptures] that bear witness to Me".  Paul makes essentially the same point in 2 Corinthians 3:1-6 when he says the way which leads "through Christ toward God" is "not of the letter, but of the Spirit; for the letter kills, but the Spirit gives life."

            Ignoring these and many similar scriptures, or glossing over their implications, leads inevitably to a conception of "Christian tradition" which loses its paradoxical character.  This happens whenever Christians exempt the Bible from the set of traditions which Christian tradition relativizes, on the grounds that the biblical text is holy and absolute because it conveys to us the absolute content of the Christian tradi­tion.  In spite of the popularity of this attitude towards the Bible, I believe this viewpoint does not provide us with a philosophically sound basis for a truly Christian tradition.  For "Christian tradition" in that case will refer to the spread and propagation of "the guidelines found in the Bible", so that Christianity is no longer the religion of the cross, the tradition centered around a self-denying person and his call to follow his Way, but the religion of the book, a tradition existing primarily for the sake of its own self-preservation.  Properly speaking, we should refer to such a viewpoint as perpetuating not Christian tradition, but biblical tradition, for it focuses more on the letter than on the spirit of the Bible.  Yet paradoxically, as we have just seen, the Bible itself is self-negating when it comes to any claim to constituting in itself an absolutely valid tradition. 

            Putting aside such aberrations of the paradoxical concept of a "Christian tradition", perhaps we should return for a moment to the nagging problem of self-reference.  Can we turn the idea of a non-traditional religious tradition back in upon itself and say that the truly Christian tradition is possible only if its proponent dies to the traditional idea that "dying to self" is the true basis of the Christian tradition?  The rather surprising answer I would like to suggest is "yes!"  For even the correct idea of a Christian tradition can be perverted if we come to see it as an end in itself. 

            If I am right in claiming that the only legitimate Christian tradi­tion is one which breaks through the boundaries of every human tradi­tion, then this means that any tradition could potentially qualify as a Christian tradition, provided its proponents are prepared to die to themselves and to their tradition--i.e., provided their tradition is "self-negating".  This, perhaps surprisingly, disqualifies many traditions--even some which would claim to be Christian because they are based on "belief in Christ" as the source of man's salvation--for it attaches "Christian" not so much to the content of a person's religious belief, as to the way in which the person holds to (or lets go of) his or her own tradition.  In this sense, there may be some grounds for suggesting that Nietzsche's philosophy is written more in the form of a Christian tradition than that of, say, Thomas Aquinas.  In any case, a self-negating tradition does not require its proponents actually to give up the whole content of their tradition, but rather that they see it in a new light, not as a self-serving means to salvation, but as one way of pointing to the One who saves.  Only in this way can any tradition be Christ-serving.

 

4. Philosophy and Christian Tradition

            At this point it might be helpful to ask why Jesus instituted a religious faith which by its very nature cannot be institutionalized, a tradition which denies the absolute validity of all traditions.  One reason might be to point out the limitations of all human endeavors, including the intellectual endeavors of philosophers and theologians.  But if this is the case, then how is philosophy relevant to truly Christian tradition?  Our answer must be twofold.  On the one hand, philosophy is harmful to Christian tradition whenever it is used merely to perpetuate one self-serving aspect of a particular tradition.  But on the other hand, it is good for Christian tradition whenever it provides a way of self-denial, or encourages the shattering of traditions, in a way which is compatible with Jesus' original vision of the Christian "tradition" of the cross.

            Now the intimate connection between Christianity and the cross does not require us to conclude that traditions as such are bad or evil.  On the contrary, traditions are in themselves potentially good vessels for expressing what philosophers might call "universal truth" or what theo­logians might call "God's will". What Jesus rejects both in his teaching and in his life is the notion that the guidelines composing any tradi­tion are ends in themselves, self-serving values.  A tradition becomes evil only when it loses sight of the super-traditional values to which it points and begins instead to point to itself.  This is why a basic task of philosophers and theologians should be to bring to light the dangers of regarding any tradition as if it were good in itself.  In so doing, regardless of the type of tradition we are examining, we will be promoting, at least indirectly, the paradox of Christian tradition.

            Interestingly, we today are actually, whether we know it or not, in the same situation as the first generation of Christian believers:  the extent to which our tradition is Christian will be directly proportional to the extent to which we believe the immanent return of Christ fulfills, and thus puts an end to, whatever tradition we associate ourselves with.  This does not mean we should all burn our books and give up our research projects in order to stand on the shore of Lake Michigan waiting to meet Jesus in the clouds!  On the contrary, I am suggesting we need to have a realistic understanding of the way in which our tradition can and will be ultimately fulfilled only when the kingdom of God is as fully established on earth as it is, or can be, in our hearts.  For the constant expectation of the fulfillment (i.e., the coming to an end) of our tradition--whatever it may be--is the attitude which will prevent us from viewing that tradition as absolute in itself.  And that expectation can be as real and as effective today as it was for the first generation of Christ's followers.

            I would like to suggest that one of the best ways of promoting this attitude is to adhere to the Socratic vision of the philosophic task, by stressing the recognition of ignorance as the starting point of all philosophy.  For only when we have distinguished clearly between what we can and cannot know will we be adequately prepared to engage in the second most important philosophical task:  the understanding of words.  By using analytic logic to describe what we can know and synthetic logic to describe what we cannot know, we can avoid innumerable errors, many of which encourage an improper attitude towards one's tradition.  On their own, these two theoretical tasks describe only half of the philo­sopher's vocation, for theory must always be relevant to, or balanced by, practice.  Without going into any detail at this point, let me simply suggest that the two basic practical tasks for the philosopher ought to be to learn how to enhance man's love of wisdom and to leave room for the experience of the wonder of silence, which alone can enable us to cope with our ignorance.

            My treatment in this paper of the paradox of the possibility of a Christian tradition has itself exemplified the theoretical side of the philosophic task.  Accordingly, I have encouraged both a recognition of our inability to resolve the problem and an explanation of the meaning of the problem in terms of synthetic logic.  I will now conclude by encouraging us to allow these logical considerations to lead us directly into the second half of the philosophic quest, by means of a correspond­ing practical question:  How is "Christian Tradition" Practically Possible?  This can be answered only by examining the traditions we are holding onto in such a way that we are preventing ourselves from realizing in practical ways what it means to be a Christian.  Of course, no philosopher can give a universal answer to this question, for each of us must answer it for ourselves.  And yet only if it encourages us to answer this question would the foregoing inquiry deserve to be regarded as part of a truly Christian philosophical tradition.  For our ability to answer this practical question will determine the extent to which we can accept our own tradition, while at the same time learning to love the wisdom which transcends and relativizes it.  And our answer will also determine the extent to which we will be willing to wait in silent expectation for the fulfillment of all traditions.

 

 


Notes to:  "How Is 'Christian Tradition' Logically Possible?"

 


 



[1]. This paper was originally written for and presented at a conference on "The Significance of Christian Tradition for Contemporary Philosophy", held at Valparaiso University, June 12-15, 1991.

[2]. The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, ed. P. Davies (New York:  Dell Publishing Co., 1969), p.732, defines "tradi­tion" as:  "1. The passing down of elements of a culture from generation to generation...  2.a. A cultural custom or usage. b. A set of such customs and usages viewed as a coherent body of precedents.  3. Any time-honored set of practices."

[3]. Quoted in W.H. Capps and W.M. Wright (eds.), Silent Fire:  An Invitation to Western Mysticism (San Francisco:  Harper & Row, Publishers, 1978), p.40.

[4]. Tillich gives a good account of the nature of symbols in Dynamics of Faith (New York:  Harper & Row, Publishers, 1957), pp.41-43.  He mentions six characteristics:  (1) A symbol is a phenomenal object or word which points beyond itself to some hidden meaning; (2) it participates in the reality to which it points; (3) it opens up new perspectives on reality; (4) it opens up new perspectives on ourselves; (5) it cannot be produced, but grows like an organism; and (6) it dies when it no longer produces a response in a community.

[5]. See my unpublished manuscript on The Geometry of Logic, and my article "Analysis and Synthesis in the Geometry of Logic", Indian Philosophical Journal (January, 1992).

[6]. Christian love (i.e., agape) is self-denying in the sense that it is always directed towards the unlovely--the person who, from the perspec­tive of ordinary human love, would be unlovable.  Most religious tradi­tions unfortunately encourage love only towards those who are lovely, those who are within one's own tradition.  But the Christian gospel, surely proclaims, if nothing else, that even the outsiders (those who are of the "world") are encompassed by God's universal love [John 3:16]. Thus, Jesus' "love your enemies" [Matt. 5:44] is a paradoxical denial of all tradi­tional notions of love.  The other side of this paradox is that we are to "hate [our] own father and mother and wife and children and brothers and sisters, yes, even [our] own life" [Luke 14:26]--i.e., anything that threatens to keep us attached to our own tradition.  It is no accident that the latter verse is followed by the warning:  "Whoever does not carry his own cross and come after me cannot be my disciple" [14:27].

[7]. I discuss the notion of a "non-political political system" and its implications in great detail in Theocracy:  A Vision of the Biblical Foundations for a Christian Political Philosophy (forthcoming).

[8]. Jesus' criticism reaches its climax in Matthew 23, where his language gets so thick, and the air so thin, as to be almost unbearable, even to our modern ears!  For example, in Matthew 23:15,33 he exclaims:  "Woe to you, scribes and Pharisees, hypocrites, because you travel about on sea and land to make one proselyte; and when he becomes one, you make him twice as much a son of hell as yourselves....  You serpents, you brood of vipers, how shall you escape the sentence of hell?"

[9]. Paul Tillich, Dynamics of Faith, p.28.

[10]. Ibid., p.29.

[11]. Ibid.

[12]. Paul Tillich, Political Expectation, ed. J.L. Adams (New York:  University Press of America, 1971), pp.58-88.

[13]. Ibid., p.65. Along these lines, Jacques Ellul argues in The Presence of the Kingdom (New York:  The Seabury Press, 1967) that "there are no such things as 'Christian principles'", since "the Person of Christ...is the principle of everything" [52].  "The Christian situation is essen­tially revolutionary" [57], so the closest we can come to a "Christian principle" would be to say, with Ellul, that it is the Christian's "absolute duty to be revolutionary" [59].

[14]. Tillich, Political Expectation, p.65.

 

 

 

 

 

 ---

This etext is based on a prepublication draft of the published version of this essay.

 

Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

 

My Web Counter identifies you as visitor number

 

 

to this page, last updated on 5 April 2011. Please come again!

 

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published articles.

 

Back to the main map of Steve Palmquist's web site.