20. POWER AND THE BOUNDARY OF POLITICS In this third part of this course we have been learning that philosophy deals not only with abstract theoretical issues relating to metaphysics, epistemology, logic, and language usage, but also with more concrete practical issues, such as those relating to science and morality. The philosophy of science and moral philosophy are both major branches of philosophy: they provide the basis for applying philosophy to more practical issues relating to specific sciences or specific ethical situations. In this and the following lecture I want us to consider one further branch of the tree of philosophy, political philosophy. There are actually a number of other fields of philosophical inquiry which, if we had time, might be included here in Part Three, such as philosophy of religion or philosophy of history. But for our purposes a discussion of political philosophy can serve as an adequate way of completing our study of how to apply philosophical thinking in our search for wisdom. Many of the philosophers we have already studied had much to say about political philosophy. For example, the main point of Plato's longest and most systematic book, called Republic, is to set out a rational plan for the ideal political system. Many aspects of his system, however, appear to modern readers to be too unrealistic and/or outdated to be considered very seriously. The suggestion that philosophers ought to be trained to serve as kings, for instance, is an idea which has rarely, if ever, been been put into practice. One of the reasons Plato's political philosophy seems so distant from our own ways of thinking about politics is that modern political thought is rooted to a large extent in the quite different ideas put forward by his star student. Aristotle's book, Politics, also contains some examples whose relevance is limited to the ancient Greek city-states (whose political systems were, by the way, the earliest forerunners of modern democracies); yet the main issues it raises are of timeless interest, transcending their original historical context in their applicability. Hence, we shall use today's lecture to take a close look at this classic text in political philosophy. Aristotle regarded politics not merely as an optional field of philosophical inquiry, but as an essential task for any philosopher, because one of the distinguishing characteristics of the human species is that "man is by nature a political animal" (Politics, p.1253a(37)). In Politics Aristotle attempted to determine what constitutes the "best" city. (The Greek word for "city", incidentally, is polis, from which we derive the word "politics".) This required him not only to discuss what its particular characteristics would be, but also to analyze the general nature of a city and the different political systems ("politeiai") which can be used to govern a city. But politeiai include not only specific governmental structures, but also "the way of life of a city" in general (1295a (133)). Although his analysis is by no means the last word on the subject, an examination of Aristotle's ideas can provide us with a good sampling of the various ways of drawing the boundary lines which define possible political systems. Aristotle began his study of politics by claiming that "every city is some form of partnership ... for the sake of some good", and that the political philosopher's task is that of "investigating what the city is composed of" (Politics, p.1252a(35)). He then pointed out that families and business relations are also examples of partnerships which exhibit something like politics on a lower level. A partnership between several families gives rise to a village, and a partnership between several villages gives rise to a city. The partnership that makes up a city therefore requires certain agreements between "similar persons, for the sake of a life that is the best possible" (1328a(209)). Aristotle never suggested that such partners must be similar in every respect, but that both unity and diversity must exist between the partners in different respects: "a city tends to come into being at the point when the partnership formed by a multitude is self-sufficient" (1261a-b(55- 57)). The purpose of a city, therefore is not [to be] a partnership in a location and for the sake of not committing injustice against each other and of transacting business. These things must necessarily be present if there is to be a city, but not even when all of them are present is it yet a city, but [the city is] the partnership in living well both of households and families for the sake of a complete and self-sufficient life. (1280b(99)) Anyone who can participate actively in the political partnership that makes up a city is qualified to be a "citizen". Thus Aristotle defined a citizen as anyone who can hold an office: "Whoever is entitled to participate in an office involving deliberation or decision is ... a citizen in this city; and the city is the multitude of such persons that is adequate with a view to a self-sufficient life" (Politics, p.1275a-b(87)). Sharing in the political partnership of the city requires the citizen not only to be a capable decision- maker, but also to be a person who is willing to abide by decisions made by others. For Aristotle's Politics (p.1277b(92)) stresses that "the good citizen should know and have the capacity both to be ruled and to rule, and this very thing is the virtue of a citizen--knowledge of rule over free persons from both [points of view]." In monarchies, where only one person rules, there are in this sense no citizens; in fact, there is technically no city and no politics either, inasmuch as there is no partnership between equals for the purpose of ruling and being ruled. This is why Aristotle sometimes contrasted monarchies with what we would call "republican" (i.e., non-monarchical) political systems: only the latter are politeiai in the strict sense of the word (though he sometimes used this term loosely to refer to monarchies as well), so republican systems occupied his primary attention in Politics. One of the most interesting aspects of Aristotle's political philosophy is that, in the course of his discussion, he developed a systematic framework consisting of six possible types of political system. They are distinguished by the different source of authority and power which characterizes each. After asserting that "the authoritative element" in a political system must "be either one or a few or the many", he explains the difference between "correct" political systems and their "deviations" (Politics, p.1279a (96): "when the one or the few or the many rule with a view to the common advantage, these political systems are necessarily correct, while those with a view to the private advantage of the one or the few or the multitude are deviations." The names Aristotle assigned each of these six systems are as follows. The correct form of "monarchy" is called a "kingship". (In ancient Greek monos means "alone" or "single"; archos means "ruler". The suffix "-cracy" comes from kratos, which means "power".) Aristotle's term for the correct form of "rule by the few" is "aristocracy", which means the power is held by the best (aristos) people. And "polity" is his term for the correct form of majority rule, though he also used this term to refer in a general way to all political systems. Since he sometimes contrasted politeiai with monarchy, Aristotle in this context probably intended politeiai to be interpreted in this narrow sense, in which case his claim is that all non-monarchical systems (i.e., all republics) can be called polities. Interestingly, in Nicomachean Ethics (p.1160a), he avoided the equivocal use of "polity" by referring to this third correct political system as "timocracy" (power held by those who own a certain amount of property (timema)). In fact, he explicitly stated that this term is to be preferred to the term "polity", even though the latter is the more common of the two terms. However, this brief account of timocracy is difficult to distinguish from oligarchy (see below); so I shall adopt the usage given in Politics in spite of its possible ambiguity. Aristotle also described three deviations from the three basically positive forms of political system: Deviations from those mentioned are tyranny from kingship, oligarchy from aristocracy, democracy from polity. Tyranny is monarchy with a view to the advantage of the monarch, oligarchy [rule] with a view to the advantage of the well off, democracy [rule] with a view to the advantage of those who are poor; none of them is with a view to the common gain. (Politics, p.1279b(96)) Let's now examine each of these six political systems in a bit more detail. In his discussion of kingship, Aristotle was careful to point out that there are several different kinds of kings. The main distinction is between those whose authority transcends the law and those who must themselves obey the law. A political system in which the "so-called king" rules "according to law" is not a true kingship; such a king is more like a "permanent general" (Politics, p.1287a(113)). A kingship in the true sense of the word is an "absolute kingship", in which "one person has authority over all matters ..., with an arrangement that resembles household management" (1285b(110-111)). In a kingship, "the best political system is not one based on written (rules) and laws", because a good king will be able to judge fairly according to the circumstances of each specific situation, being guided by the general principles of the law, even though his judgment need not be determined by them (1286a(111)). As Aristotle put it in Politics, p.1284a(106-107): "If there is one person so outstanding by his excess of virtue--or a number of persons ...-- .. such persons can no longer be regarded as a part of the city.... [For] they themselves are law." He then pointed out that "ostracism" is the inevitable fate for such persons "in the deviant political systems" (1284b(108)), even though in "the best political systems ... persons of this sort will be permanent kings in their cities." Although kingship would be the best political system, Aristotle preferred aristocracy for several reasons. There is always a danger that the one man holding all the power will turn bad, so that the best system would degenerate into the worst (i.e., tyranny). The only protection against such a man being overcome by his own selfish desires is for him to accept the rule of law; thus "it is laws--correctly enacted--that should be authoritative", not persons (Politics, pp.1282a-b(103)). The nature of law is such that it protects people against the ever-present danger of being corrupted by their own appetite, for as Aristotle explained (1287a(114)): "One who asks law to rule ... is held to be asking god and intellect alone to rule, while one who asks man adds the beast. Desire is a thing of this sort; and spiritedness perverts rulers and the best men. Hence law is intellect without appetite." Another problem with kingship in Aristotle's mind is that there is likely to be more than just one good man in most cities, so the good men who are not allowed to rule will not be satisfied with the inequality between themselves and the king. Such an unjust situation is almost inevitably resolved by replacing the king with an aristocracy, in which all the rulers are good men (Politics, p.1286b(112)). (They cannot be good women because, according to Aristotle, women are not even be allowed to become citizens.) Hence, Aristotle suggested that the less power a king has (i.e., the less he is like a true king), the longer he will be able to preserve his rule (1313a(173)). An "aristocracy ... is in some sense an oligarchy" (oligos means "few"), since in both types of political systems "the rulers are few" (Politics, p.1306b(159)). The difference is that, unlike a typical (i.e., deviant) oligarchy, in which the rulers are chosen merely "on the basis of wealth", the rulers in an aristocracy are chosen "in accordance with virtue" (1273a(82)). (When property ownership is the type of wealth used as one of the main qualifications for choosing who is given the power and authority to rule in an oligarchy (see e.g., pp.1279b(96)), the system could also be called a timocracy. One way of accounting for the potential ambiguity between the terms "oligarchy" and "timocracy" would be to note that a timocracy would be a polity if the amount of property required to be a citizen is very low, whereas it would be an oligarchy if the amount is high, since only a few people would then be wealthy enough to be citizens.) Oligarchy is usually bad for a city, because there is no guarantee that the rulers will be virtuous (e.g., by looking after the welfare of the poor) just because they are rich. An aristocracy, by contrast, is by definition (in Aristotle's sense of the word) a political system in which the few men who are given the power and authority to rule will, being virtuous, look after those who are not members of the ruling class. The distinction to which Aristotle devoted the most attention in Politics is that between the two extreme forms of non-monarchical government, oligarchy and democracy. This is probably because these two systems are the ones found most frequently in real historical cities (both in ancient Greece and in modern times). For example, he said "law may be oligarchic or democratic" (Politics, p.1281a (100)), in the sense that "in democratic political systems the people have authority, while by contrast it is the few in oligarchies" (1278b(94)). In Politics, pp.1279b(96)-1280a(97), he continued: oligarchy is when those with property have authority in the political system; and democracy is the opposite, when those have authority who do not possess a [significant] amount of property but are poor ... What makes democracy and oligarchy differ is poverty and wealth: wherever some rule on account of wealth, whether a minority or a majority, this is necessarily an oligarchy, and wherever those who are poor, a democracy. But it turns out ... that the former are few and the latter many ... Whereas "the defining principle of aristocracy is virtue" and "that of oligarchy is wealth", the defining principle of democracy is "the majority [i.e., the poor] having authority" (1310a(167)). Democracy is the political system in which a partnership between the "common people" (demos) determines how power and authority are distributed in the city. It is therefore characterized by a type of "freedom" that involves "being ruled and ruling in turn" (Politics, p.1317a-b(183)). Such an arrangement of reciprocal ruling among equals "is law" (1287a(113)). As with most of the other political systems, Aristotle discussed several varieties of democracy, including the type in which "the people become a monarch", in the sense that "the many have authority [over the law, though] not as individuals but all together" (1292a(125-6)). In the narrow sense of a political system (i.e., as excluding monarchies), "a democracy of this sort is not a political system. For where the laws do not rule there is no political system." Aristotle warned that the best political system for a given city cannot be determined in advance: any of the systems (except tyranny) may end up being the most appropriate, once the specific situation is taken into consideration. Thus, for example, he admitted that sometimes a kingship will be the best system for a city, even though in general "to have law rule is to be chosen in preference to having one of the citizens do so" (Politics, p.1288a(115-116)). The political system Aristotle thought is most often to be preferred, which he called "polity", is midway between aristocracy and democracy. Yet even in the case of polity, he granted that "there is nothing to prevent another political system being more advantageous for certain [cities]" (1296b(136)). Polity is a political system based on Aristotle's famous principle of the "golden mean" (see e.g., Ethics, pp.1106a(65)-1109b(75)), which tells us always to avoid extremes, or in this case tells us that "the middling sort of life is best" for both the city and the individual (Politics, p.1295a(133)). In other words, polity is a political system in which what we would call the "middle class" forms a majority of people who have the power and authority to rule in a way that mixes elements of the other three republican systems. The mixture Aristotle had in mind involves a combination of democracy and oligarchy (the two extremes) in such a way that their extreme elements will cancel each other out: a polity requires "a mixture of ... the well off and the poor" (1293b(129)-1294b(132)). But it might also mix elements of aristocracy and oligarchy, as when a polity requires "a law distributing offices on the basis of merit [as in aristocracy] to those who are well off [as in oligarchy]" (1288a(116)). When we read Aristotle saying that the best sort of oligarchy "is very close to so-called polity" (1320b(190)), we must assume this good oligarchy is actually an aristocracy. For aristocracy and polity are the "means" between the "extremes" of oligarchy and democracy. With this in mind, we can now map the relations between the four republican (non-monarchical) political systems, by using either a simple flow chart (as in Figure 20.1a), or a 2LAR cross (as in Figure 20.1b), in which the two underlying questions are (1) Are there only a few rulers? and (2) Is the system good (i.e., "correct")? (a) As a Flow Chart (b) Mapped onto the Cross [Figure 20.1: The Four Forms of Republican Political Systems] These maps help us to see why Aristotle sometimes virtually equated polity with aristocracy (e.g., Politics, pp.1286b(112)); for these systems, as the "means", would be good for most cities, while democracy and oligarchy, as the "extremes", would be bad. The remaining political system in Aristotle's framework is "tyranny", which is technically the opposite of (i.e., deviation from) kingship. Yet Aristotle also called it "the extreme form of democracy", and added that some forms of oligarchy and democracy are "tyrannies", divided among many persons (Politics, p.1312b(172)). He explained the relation between tyranny and the other two deviant political systems as follows (1310b(168)-1311a(169)): Kingship accords with aristocracy, while tyranny is composed of the ultimate sort of oligarchy and of democracy--hence it is composed of the two bad political systems and involves the deviations and errors of both of them.... .... Having wealth as its end comes from oligarchy ..., as does its distrust of the multitude.... From democracy comes their war on the notables .. He then explained why kingship is not worth the risk of tyranny (1313a(173)): Kingships no longer arise today; if monarchies do arise, they tend to be tyrannies. This is because kingship is a voluntary sort of rule ..., but [nowadays] there are many persons who are similar, with none of them so outstanding as to match the extent and the claim to merit of the office. If we now add the two forms of monarchy to the four forms of republican political systems, we can put all six systems together in the form of a circular flow chart, enabling us to see the entire framework at a single glance. [Figure 20.2: Aristotle's Six Forms of Political Systems] In his discussion of political revolutions, Aristotle argued that, although each system can change into virtually any other system, they tend to "undergo revolution more frequently into their opposite than into a political system of a neighboring sort" (Politics, pp.1316a-b(179-80)). In other words, a revolution is more likely to be influenced by the internal logic of the relation between different political systems than by the empirical factor of what type of system is in effect in a neighboring city. In Politics, p.1286b(112), Aristotle described more fully how the progression of political systems, as represented by the arrows in Figure 20.2, typically works itself out in real historical situations: political systems normally start out as kingships, pass over into aristocracies or polities, degenerate into oligarchies, fall into the grips of a tyranny, and are liberated from oppression by a democracy. Even though moving "from an aristocracy" to "a democracy" does "harm to the political system" (1270b(76)), he regarded democracy as the almost inevitable political system, inasmuch as it serves as the best protection against tyranny. Yet Aristotle's own hope was that this historical fact can be overcome by reason, with the result that the least extreme of the truly good systems, polity, can become a reality, even though it had rarely existed in the past. This progression can also be mapped onto a 6CR triangle (with a few extra arrows added) by placing the three "good" systems on the upward-pointing triangle and the three "bad" systems [Figure 20.3: Aristotle's Framework as a 6CR] on the downward-pointing triangle, as in Figure 20.3. The lines pointing upward to polity are dashed in order to represent the difficulty of reaching this ideal system. Aristotle's helpful summary of his framework for political systems in Book VIII, Chapter 10 of Nicomachean Ethics adds several additional points worth mentioning in conclusion. Here kingship is treated as the best option, for any truly good king will always have the best interests of his subjects in mind. Since he has absolute power and authority over all the people, no one will be able to prevent the king from putting his good will into practice. Even though an aristocracy consists of the "best" men, it is not as good as kingship, because it is more likely that a few bad men will infiltrate the aristocracy and corrupt the intentions of the otherwise good rulers. And when all property owners are allowed to influence the way laws are formed and rights are distributed among the citizens, such corruption becomes even more likely. Aristotle compared the relationship between the citizen and the city in these three good political systems to three types of family relationships. In kingship the king is like a father and the citizen is like a son. In aristocracy the ruling class is like a husband and the other citizens are like a wife. And in timocracy (or polity) the relationship between property owners is like that between siblings. But, just as family relationships are not always harmonious, each of these political systems can be perverted, thus giving rise to tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy, respectively. Kingship is the most risky option, because "the worst is that which is the opposite to the best." When choosing a political system, we must therefore keep in mind that when we aim at a particular system, we might end up with its opposite instead. This is why, as we have seen, Aristotle elsewhere defended polity (i.e., timocracy) as the safest option: even if it slips into democracy, the negative effect on the average citizen is kept to a minimum, since democracy is "the least bad" of the three bad political systems. In a "majority rules" system the will of the majority is likely to be influenced by the selfish motives of the many bad people who live in any society, but to some extent this will be balanced by the good motives of the virtuous people. Our time is now up for this session. But I will begin the final lecture in Part Three by assessing some of the rather surprising conclusions and implications of Aristotle's political system. We shall then look at some of the other options for political systems which, for one reason or another, Aristotle did not consider. QUESTIONS FOR FURTHER THOUGHT 1. What is power? 2. Is anarchy ("no ruler") a political system? 3. Where does law come from? 4. Is absolute freedom possible? RECOMMENDED READINGS 1. Aristotle, The Politics, tr. Carnes Lord (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1984), passim, but see especially Book 4, Chapter 2 (=1289a-b). 2. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, tr. J.A.K. Thomson in The Ethics of Aristotle (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1953), especially Book VIII, Chapter 10, pp.1160a-1161a. 3. Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, tr. G. Bull (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1961). 4. Antoine de Saint-Exupery, The Little Prince, tr. Katherine Woods (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1943).