26.  ANGST AND THE PARADOX OF COURAGE





    The deepest question of all ontology is:  Why is there something

(i.e., being) rather than nothing (i.e., non-being)?  This question is the

ultimate basis of all existential wonder.  For the question, Why is the

world here? leads directly to the question, Why am I here? and from there

to a host of questions about the meaning of life.  Questions of the latter

sort have been the most frequent types of questions addressed in my

students' insight papers. This is particularly true once we recognize that

most questions about death are also, at least indirectly, questions about

the meaning of life.  For the awareness of non-being first raises the

question of being; and in the same way the awareness of death first raises

the question of the meaning of life.  In the next lecture we will examine

the paradox which arises out of our search for life's meaning in the face

of the inevitability of death.  But today we will focus on another,

closely related paradox, which arises within us any time we choose life in

the face of death.



    According to most existentialists, any time we come face to face with

the possibility of our own non-being (e.g., as when we reflect upon our

eventual death), we have a natural "existential response" involving a very

special kind of fear.  Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), a German

existentialist philosopher who, with Wittgenstein, is generally regarded

as one of the two most influential twentieth-century philosophers,

distinguished between this special existential fear and ordinary kinds of

fear in the following way.  Ordinary fear is a person's empirical response

to a threatening object within the world: it usually requires us either to

fight the object in hopes of overpowering its threat, or to flee from the

object in hopes of escaping from its threat.  In both cases we can say the

person who is afraid of something in the world responds by trying to push

something out of the world--either the feared object or one's own self

(see Figure 26.1a).  By contrast, existential fear is a response in the

depths of a person's being to the general human situation, especially when

that situation reveals within us the presence of non-being or

"nothingness" in some way.  The natural human response is to flee from the

threat, since it seems impossible to fight against "nothing"!  But in this

case we flee not by seeking to escape the world, but by immersing

ourselves more fully into the empirical objects of our ordinary experience

(see Figure 26.1b). This may be done in many ways, such as by pursuing

hobbies, watching television, becoming an avid sports fan, or even

becoming a scholar and immersing oneself in books.  Heidegger's point is

that the usual (unhealthy) way of escaping from the threat of non-being is

merely to pretend it is not there, by immersing oneself in being.



    Using Heidegger's distinction as an introduction, let us now look back

to the ideas of an earlier philosopher, who also had much to say about the

nature and function of existential fear.  The philosopher who is generally

recognized as the father of theistic existentialism (as opposed to the

atheistic existentialism fathered by Nietzsche) is Smren Kierkegaard

(1813-1855). Kierkegaard (pronounced "Keerkagore", meaning

"churchyard"--i.e., graveyard) was a lonely Danish philosopher who wrote

twenty-one books (as well as 8000 pages of unpublished papers) in twelve

short years, and whose ideas were never well received during his own

lifetime.  His main philosophical ideas were developed in a series of

books written under several different pseudonyms (in some of which he

argued against his own ideas!).  But in the last few years of his life he

wrote a number of books using his own name, in which he attacked the

corruptions he perceived in the Christianity of his day.  Of his many

interesting ideas, the only one we will have time to investigate here is

his use of the Danish word "angst" to refer to what I have called

"existential fear".

 



(a) Ordinary Empirical Fear     (b) Existential Fear ("Angst")



[Figure 26.1:  Inappropriate Responses to Two Kinds of Fear]



    Although angst is sometimes translated as "dread" or "anxiety",

neither of these words captures the full depth of the existential fear of

non-being which Kierkegaard intended this word to denote.  Dread is too

often associated with extreme displeasure or apprehension at the thought

of facing some empirical threat, as when I say I dread going to the

dentist.  Likewise, anxiety is too often associated with ordinary

"stress", as when students say they feel anxious about their ability to

pass the upcoming examination.  In order to guard against the temptation

to connect angst too closely with ordinary empirical types of fear, many

scholars have adopted the habit of simply using the original Danish

word--a practice I shall follow today.  When I do refer on several

occasions to dread or anxiety, we should, of course, identify these with

angst, not empirical fear.



    Kierkegaard's first book, Either-Or (1843), distinguished between two

basic ways of life, the aesthetic and the ethical.  The former is based on

feelings and focuses on enjoying the pleasures of life; the latter is

based on duty and focuses on doing what is good.  As such, this

distinction corresponds to the distinction we discussed in Lecture 18,

between utilitarianism and deontology. At first, those who read the book

debated over which of these two opposing points of view the author

actually wished to support.  But Kierkegaard's true intention was to

demonstrate that either choice on its own is as absurd or incomplete as

the other.  For he later published another book, Stages on Life's Way

(1845), wherein he argued that the aesthetic and ethical stages both point

beyond themselves to a third stage, the religious, which synthesizes and

surpasses the two earlier stages (see Figure 26.2).  He defined the

religious way of life in terms of an attitude of "inwardness", which

transcends the "outwardness" required for theoretical reasoning and

scientific knowledge.



    In The Concept of Anxiety (1844) Kierkegaard developed his idea of

angst by analyzing the Christian idea of sin.  Angst, he claimed, is a

psychological state arising naturally out of the essential, ontological

nature of man:  our freedom gives us infinite potential for the future;

yet our presence in time makes us finite and ignorant.  In other words,

angst arises out of the tension between the sensuousness of our body

(rooted as it is in time) and the freedom of our soul (rooted as it is in

eternity). Our ignorance insures



[Figure 26.2:  Kierkegaard's Three Stages and Two Leaps]



that the choices we make for our own future will eventually plunge us into

sin, so that angst comes to be experienced as "entangled freedom"

(p.320)--that is, as the infinite tangled up in the finite.  Sin, then, as

the normal state of the human spirit (see Figure 26.3), is the first of

two "qualitative leaps" we must make in order to progress through the

stages of life.  After leaping from innocence to sin (as in the story of

Adam and Eve), the second leap is from sin to faith (as in the story of

Abraham).  The first leap corresponds to the change from the aesthetic to

the ethical (or vice versa), while the second corresponds to the change

from the aesthetic/ethical choice to the religious (see Figure 26.2).

Paganism is rooted in the aesthetic stage, where the leap of sin is

experienced as fate and the leap of faith as providence; Judaism, by

contrast, is rooted in the ethical stage, where the leap of sin is

experienced as guilt and the leap of faith as atonement.  Christianity

surpasses both of these by actually being rooted in the properly religious

stage of absolute faith in God.



[Figure 26.3:  The Ontological Origins of Angst and Sin]



    Kierkegaard's analysis of angst and sin suggests that the lack of

angst is the worst possible psychological state, since without angst we

could never progress to the stage of spirit.  In the original state of

innocence angst arises as a response to the "nothing" (i.e., the person's

ignorance) of the future:  "anxiety is freedom's actuality as the

possibility of possibility" (p.313).  To ignore this freedom is actually

idolatry when it causes the person in the aesthetic stage of life to grasp

innocence, peace, happiness, beauty, etc., as if they were good in and of

themselves.  For to do so is to separate oneself from the spiritual depths

of one's own human nature:  "The most effective means of escaping

spiritual trial is to become spiritless" (p.385). Yet once this freedom is

utilized, an awareness of sin arises, which causes a new kind of angst, in

the form of "anxiety about evil" (pp.381-386).  This comes in three forms:

(1) the desire to return to a state of innocence; (2) the threat of

falling deeper into sin; and (3) the wish that mere repentance were enough

to atone for sin.  Unfortunately, the attempt of many religious people to

overcome such anxiety by means of outward goodness only gives rise to more

angst, in the form of "anxiety about the good" (pp.386-420).



    The truly religious person turns away from both aesthetic and ethical

aims in order to become inward.  "Inwardness" refers to immediate

self-understanding in action (p.408), which requires a person to be open

to the eternal in one's own self.  To turn towards oneself in this way is

therefore identical to turning towards God.  As a result, it always begins

by heightening a person's awareness of guilt (pp.376-377):



In turning toward himself, [the religious "genius"] eo ipso turns toward

God, and ... when the finite spirit would see God, it must begin as

guilty.  As he turns toward himself, he discovers guilt.  The greater the

genius, the more profoundly he discovers guilt....



    In turning inward he discovers freedom....



    To the degree he discovers freedom, to that same degree the anxiety of

sin is upon him in the state of possibility....



Such a person will then recognize that anxiety really points beyond itself

to faith (p.385):



The only thing that is truly able to disarm the sophistry of sin is faith,

courage to believe that the state [of sin] itself is a new sin, courage to

renounce anxiety without anxiety, which only faith can do; faith does not

thereby annihilate anxiety, but ... extricates itself from anxiety's

moment of death.



In other words, the proper response to anxiety is to stop being anxious

about anxiety, accepting it in the belief that it exists for a higher

purpose. Whereas pagan anxiety expresses itself most profoundly as fate,

and Jewish anxiety as guilt, the anxiety of the true Christian (whom

Kierkegaard regarded as practicing the most advanced form of religion) is

therefore expressed in the form of suffering.



    Kierkegaard argued that the key to solving the problem of angst is to

learn to face it courageously, with the paradoxical feelings of

"sympathetic antipathy" and "antipathetic sympathy" (p.313).  Anyone who

"has learned to be anxious in the right way has learned the ultimate"

(p.421).  For "anxiety is through faith absolutely educative, because it

consumes all finite ends" (p.422).  Despite its apparently negative

character, the suffering caused by angst is therefore essential to our

spiritual growth:  "the more profoundly he is in anxiety, the greater is

the man" (p.421).  Kierkegaard had numerous other philosophical insights,

not only concerning the human experience of angst, but also about numerous

other topics, such as the paradoxical relationship between history (the

finite) and subjectivity (the infinite), and the true nature of Christian

faith as requiring a subjective willingness to die.  However, we will be

unable to pursue these or other interesting topics here.



    Instead, I want to point out that, given Kierkegaard's analysis of

angst, the relationship between dread and death is analogous to the

relationship between love and life:  just as love is the moving power of

life, so also dread is the moving power of death.  Whereas the former is

the power of being, driving us towards the unity of opposites, the latter

is the power of non- being, driving us towards the diversity of opposites.

In other words, dread is the driving power behind the "estrangement" which

Tillich regarded as the necessary prerequisite for love (see Figure 25.1).

The struggle between these two powers is, in fact, what keeps us alive,

while at the same time giving us a glimpse of our eternality in the midst

of our finitude.  In other words, dread, in spite of being a primarily

negative experience, reminds us of our capacity for self-transcendence.

Together, the powers of love and dread remind us that, on the one hand, we

are not at home in this world, and yet on the other hand, we are not

entirely strangers either.  Recognizing this paradox can help us to

respond to real experiences of angst in a way which is appropriate to the

eternal dimension of our lives.



    The failure to balance the powers of eternality (love) and temporality

(death) in our lives usually results is some type of psychological

disturbance, and can eventually lead even to insanity.  Insanity does not

come from paying too much attention to the paradoxes of human experiences;

rather, it results from the attempt to run away from them to the security

of either the infinite or the finite on its own.  As long as the two

powers are engaged in a struggle within us, our mental health will be

preserved.  But the loss of either eternality or temporality can drive a

person insane:  for the former would limit us to an application of

analytic logic, thereby causing us to see the world as an unbearable

diversity of fragmented and disconnected bits, while the latter would

limit us to an application of synthetic logic, thereby causing us to see

the world as an unbearable unity, without discrete and intelligible parts.

The former describes the form of insanity that stems from an overemphasis

on reason over imagination, as when paranoid schizophrenics interpret

their experience within a narrow set of limits (e.g., "everyone is against

me"); the latter describes the form of insanity that stems from an

overemphasis on imagination over reason, as when the elderly lose

themselves in the limitlessness of senility.



    Tillich argued that we are all guilty of losing our eternality to some

extent.  The best explanation for the angst we feel when we think honestly

about our own death, he claimed, is that we all know deep down inside that

we deserve to die, because of the unauthentic way we have lived.  Too

often, people's response to this guilt is merely to flee from it into the

safety of philosophical arguments for immortality or a religious hope for

eternal life. Yet the latter only increases the philosopher's

over-dependence on logical reasoning, while the former only increases the

believer's over-dependence on religious imagination.  In other words,

these common "solutions", though not in themselves wrong, can sometimes

backfire by intensifying the loss of eternality that comes from denying

one side of the paradox.



    The only proper response to the loss of eternality revealed in our

experience of existential dread is, according to Tillich, to face the

threat of non-being with an existential courage to be.  In his book, The

Courage To Be (1952), he described this response in the following way

(p.152-153):



Courage is the self-affirmation of being in spite of the fact of

non-being.  It is the act of the individual self in taking the anxiety of

non-being upon itself by affirming itself ...  Courage always includes a

risk, it is always threatened by non-being ...  Courage needs the power of

being, a power transcending the non-being which is experienced in the

anxiety of fate and death, ... in the anxiety of emptiness and

meaninglessness, ... [and] in the anxiety of guilt and condemnation.  The

courage which takes this threefold anxiety into itself must be rooted in a

power of being that is greater than the power of oneself and the power of

one's world....  There are no exceptions to this rule; and this means that

every courage to be has openly or covertly a religious root.  For religion

is the state of being grasped by the power of being itself.



Like Kierkegaard, Tillich therefore saw the threat of non-being as an

existential problem whose only adequate solution is essentially religious.

This word "religious" should not be misunderstood as referring to

religious practices, such as going to church, singing hymns, etc.  For

such things can be misused to keep us away from truly religious courage.

Instead, the point here is that to be religious means to be open to an

experience of a Being who, by transcending the distinction between being

and non-being, can alone supply us with the courage to be.



    This basic experience of receiving the gift of the courage to be is

closely related, according to Tillich, both to mystical experiences of

participation in God, and to more ordinary experiences of a personal

encounter between man and God.  Such experiences are rooted in a

recognition that the presence of non- being within us estranges us from

our true nature, and that this problem can be solved only if we are

willing to be "grasped by the power of being itself" (p.153).  For only

when we "participate in something which transcends the self" (p.161) will

we be prepared to experience the most profound manifestation of the

courage to be, in the form of the "courage to accept acceptance" (pp.159-

166). This courageous self-affirmation is not merely "the Existentialist

courage to be as oneself.  It is the paradoxical act in which one is

accepted by that which infinitely transcends one's individual self."  Nor

does this ultimate acceptance require us to deny our guilt, for "it is not

the good or the wise or the pious who are entitled to the courage to

accept acceptance but those who are lacking in all these qualities and are

aware of being unacceptable" (pp.160-161).



    At the beginning of the process of accepting acceptance, the courage

to be is experienced merely as the bare "courage of despair [i.e., of

angst]" (p.170):



the acceptance of despair is in itself faith on the boundary line of the

courage to be.  In this situation the meaning of life is reduced to

despair about the meaning of life.  But as long as this despair is an act

of life it is positive in its negativity.



Eventually, by living our life in the paradoxical power of the courage to

be, we will finally be ready to welcome death itself not as a tragic

confirmation of angst, but as the final step in this life-long process.

Along these lines, Tillich claimed that Plato's arguments for the

immortality of the soul were "attempts to interpret the courage of

Socrates", who had clearly recognized that "the courage to die is the test

of the courage to be" (p.164).  We will look more fully at the experience

of death itself in the following lecture. For now, however, it will

suffice merely to summarize Tillich's theory of courage in terms of the

map given in Figure 26.4.



    The religious basis of the courageous acceptance of life in the face

of death, of being in spite of the dreadful prospects of non-being, is

made explicit in the biblical notion of the "fear of the Lord".  The Old

Testament references to fearing God are too often watered down to the

point where they are taken to mean nothing more than being careful to obey

the Law lest we be punished.  But they refer far more profoundly to the

fact that the God of the Old Testament, as the Being who holds all beings

in His hand, is the ultimate source of life and death; as such, the one

who is courageous enough to approach such a Being must do so with the

utmost reverence and awe.  As Mitchell put it: "Fear of the Lord is being

in awe, aware of the shocking, silent, presence of God"



[Figure 26.4:  Existential Courage in the Face of Non-Being]



(In Pursuit of Wonder, p.75)--a comment reminiscent of Otto's notion of

awe in the presence of the numinous (see Lecture 23, pp.168-169).

Throughout the Bible this fundamental, other-worldly fear is depicted as

an existential response to the human situation which, if we accept it,

will give us otherwise unattainable strength in coping with the fearful

situations that arise in the ordinary world.  This could indeed be

regarded as the basic message of the Psalms and Proverbs:  "The fear of

the Lord is the beginning of wisdom" (e.g., Psalm 111:10; Proverbs 1:7)

means we will learn best how to respond to the threats within the world

only when we have courageously responded to the threat outside the world.

In other words, angst and wisdom are best regarded, paradoxically, as two

sides of the same coin.



    If we do not merely ignore the basic ontological question raised at

the beginning of this lecture, then we seem to have a choice between two

possible answers:  either the existence of the world is meaningless and

the courage to be has no basis, or else there is a God who is,

paradoxically, beyond the very distinction between something and nothing,

and who thereby lends meaning to both being and non-being, thus forming

the ultimate basis of faith, and so also of our courage to be.  But as

Kierkegaard, Tillich, and many other religious existentialists have

pointed out, this God cannot lend meaning merely by being a doctrine

imposed on us by the social pressures of a religious community; rather, we

must experience God as a reality that gives us power to cope with the

paradoxes of life, providing us with faith in the face of doubt, peace in

the face of turmoil, acceptance in the face of guilt, and courage in the

face of dread.





QUESTIONS FOR FURTHER THOUGHT



1. Could Figure 26.1 be revised to depict appropriate responses to the two

kinds of fear?



2. Is it possible to choose both the aesthetic and the ethical ways of

life?



3. Is it necessary for human beings to sin?



4. Does angst actually help us to cope with ordinary, empirical fears?





RECOMMENDED READINGS



1. Smren Kierkegaard, The Concept of Anxiety:  A simple psychologically

orienting deliberation on the dogmatic issue of hereditary sin, tr. Reidar

Thomte and Albert B. Anderson (Princeton:  Princeton University Press,

1980), especially section 5, "The Concept of Anxiety", pp.313-316.  (Page

numbers refer to the original Danish pagination, as cited in the margins

of this translation.)



2. Paul Tillich, The Courage To Be (London:  Collins, 1952), especially

Chapter VI, "Courage and Transcendence", pp.152-183.



3. Ernest Becker, The Denial of Death (New York:  The Free Press, 1973).



4. Douglas N. Walton, Courage:  A philosophical investigation (Los

Angeles: University of California Press, 1986).