12.Philosophers in the Public Square:

A Religious Resolution of Kant’s Conflict of the Faculties

 

Prof. Stephen Palmquist, D.Phil. (Oxon)

Department of Religion and Philosophy

Hong Kong Baptist University

(stevepq@hkbu.edu.hk)

With an Appendix co-authored by Richard W. Mapplebeckpalmer

 

1. On Retreat With Kant: Concord and Conflict in Philosophical Practice

In opposition to the common belief that philosophy is a discipline belonging solely in the university, where it can be safely insulated from influencing or beinginfluenced by the way ordinary people live their lives, a movement has arisen over the past decade or so, commonly known as “Philosophical Practice.” Some trace its early organization back to 1992, when several French philosophers and friends casually met one Sunday morning in a Paris café to discuss an issue of mutual concern. A journalist, overhearing them planning a follow-up meeting and mistakenly thinking it would be open tothe general public, announced it in the local press, and the first “Café Philo” was born. Soon the popularity of the weekly gatherings that began cropping up in cafés all over Paris and throughout France came to the attention of philosophers elsewhere, who had already been interested in practical ways of luring philosophy out of the Academy and back into the public square (where it began, in pre-Platonic Athens). Contacts were made between counselors who were already using philosophical ideas and methods to assist clients in overcoming personal problems, consultants who had already been hired by big businesses to assist them in thinking philosophically about various corporate problems, and teachers who were already interested in minimizing current social problems by introducing “philosophy for children” into primary and secondary school curricula. Starting in 1995,annual conferences began to be held, where philosophers engaged in these and other non-academic activities could share their ideas and encourage others to regard philosophy as more than just an academic discipline.

Soon after attending the Third International Conference on Philosophical Practice, in July of 1997, Ibegan exploring various ways of involving myself in philosophical activities outside the university. At that conference, I read a paper[1] pointing out that the psychologist Carl Jung was strongly influenced by Kant and arguing that certain Kantian ideas could also serve as useful counseling tools. In addition to experimenting with this possibility myself in some volunteer counseling I did over the next few years, I started the Hong Kong Philosophy Café in 1999an organization that has now grown to five semi-independent branches with a mailing list of over 400 interested participants.[2] Meanwhile, in 1998 I had acquired aten-acre parcel of forest nestled in the backwoods of Mendocino County, about150 miles north of San Francisco, with the idea of setting up a philosophical retreat center—an idea that developed out of discussions I had with various participants attending the 1997 conference. In January of 2001 the first CIPHER[3] retreat took place in a newly completed house that had been built on the property.

For a Kant scholar accustomed to working in a university setting, these new exploits have been both exciting and challenging. They have forced me to think deeply about whether (and if so, how) Kant’s ideas can be useful to ordinary laypersons. As a result, I have come to a new understanding of the false limitations philosophers put upon themselves when they buy into the assumption that philosophy should be tucked safely away in the inner recesses of the Academy. With the idea of testing the applicability and interest Kant’s ideas might have to the general public, I facilitated a one-day retreat in December of 2001, intended as a way of coming to terms with the September 11thtragedy and the resulting war in Afghanistan that was then unfolding. Four local residents, all ordinary working people none of whom had previous exposureto Kant, met with me for four intense, two-hour sessions of reading and discussion based on Kant’s essay, Perpetual Peace. The success of the event was evidentnot only from the numerous insights that arose during our discussions, but alsofrom the concord wefive experienced, and came to hope for the world at large, as a result ofconsidering Kant’s explanation of why war happens and his vision of theway political relations could some day do without it.

The success ofthat event (and other retreats) motivated me to plan a second retreat on Kant,this time offering scholars an opportunity to reflect in a non-academic settingon a text where Kant appears to be less optimistic about the possibility (oreven the desirability) of concord: The Conflict of the Faculties. Since the focus of my recent researchon Kant had been in the area of the religious and theological implications ofhis philosophy, and since I was already involved in the project of co-editingthe present collection of essays, a retreat discussing how Kant’s Conflict offers important guidelines forinterpreting his philosophy of religion seemed like a good idea. Four of thefive participants in the retreat, held in mid-July of 2002, subsequentlysubmitted essays for this volume. As it turned out, however, our discussionsfocused as much on Kant’s conception of what a philosopher should be, andon how the philosophy facultyof a university should relate to the rest of the university and (especially) tothe general public, as on the specific details of Kant’s philosophy ofreligion—if not more so.

In the secondsection of this essay, I shall provide a report on the discussions held at theJuly 2002 CIPHER retreat, entitled “Rethinking Kant’s Philosophy ofReligion.” This report will not identify the participants who expressedspecific ideas, for in most cases the insights were mutual, arisingspontaneously as a result of the concord that developed between us through theprolonged attention we were able to give, as a small group of new friendsphilosophizing together in a relaxed and non-combative setting, to Kant’stext. In §3 I shall then take a step back from the focus on Kant as atopic discussed at philosophical retreats and summarize my overall strategy forinterpreting Kant, explaining how and why it provides a strong basis forinterpreting his philosophy of religion in an affirmative way. In §4 Iargue that one of the best non-academic professions for a Kantian philosopherto enter would be that of a pastor. The essay then concludes with an Appendix,co-authored by a pastor-philosopher who actually implements many of the ideaspresented here.

 

2.Kant on the Philosopher’s Responsibility to the General Public

In his lastpublished work on religion, Part I of The Conflict of the Faculties (1798), Kant provides numerous helpfulclarifications of his previously published views on religion. He bases many ofhis arguments on a theory of the fundamental difference between theresponsibilities philosophers and theologians have in their respectiverelationships to the government on one hand and to the general public on theother. In this respect, the main difference between philosophers andtheologians, he argues, is that the latter are charged with the task oftraining one of the three “businessmen of the faculties” (i.e., pastors), whereas philosophers have no suchresponsibility to train public servants.[4]

Kant’stheory of the difference between philosophers and theologians raises two fundamentalquestions for anyone interested in promoting a harmonious relationship betweenthe disciplines of theology (and/or religion) and philosophy: (1) Dophilosophers have anyproper role as public servants, or are they necessarily confined to theuniversity, where they serve merely as critics of the other three faculties?and (2) Would it be possible and/or desirable for a pastor, who presumably mustdon the cloak of the theology faculty, also to be a practicing philosopher inKant’s sense (i.e., one whose allegiance is to “barereason”)? Exploring how Kant answers the first question in Conflict will be the purpose of this section.After §3 outlines Kant’s general understanding of the relationshipphilosophy has to the higher faculty of theology and to the public practice ofreligion, we will be prepared to answer the second question in §4.

Before lookingat Kant’s views on the philosopher’s responsibility to the public,we must address the issue Kant raises in the Preface of Conflict, regarding his own readiness to complywith the deceased king’s demand that he remain silent on matters relatingto religion. As is well known, the censor for the highly conservative kingobjected to the theology in Kant’s 1793 book, Religion within theBounds of Bare Reason,and ordered Kant to stop writing on religious matters. In his response Kant didnot accept the charges; rather, he claimed his approach was designed to defendand promote the Christian religion.[5] Nevertheless, he agreed not only to stopwriting on religion, but even to stop speaking in public on any religiousmatter as long as he remained the king’s servant. Fortunately, the king died before Kantdid, and Kant argued that this freed him from his promise to remain silent.Kant was therefore able in good conscience[6] to publish this important last work,containing his most mature reflections on religion and theology. Was Kantjustified (when judged by the principles of his own philosophy) in taking this“easy way out” in his conflict with the government? Kant’s theoryof the distinctive role of philosophers seems partially designed to exoneratehim from any charge of cowardice: he was merely following his duty as theking’s loyal servant. However, as we shall see, this strategy does notsucceed, when properly understood.

At theretreat, we discerned four distinctive tiers or levels in Kant’s accountof the philosopher’s role. The first and most general level is thatoccupied by the general public. By “public” Kant means anythingoutside both the university and the government that is potentially a concernfor everyone—that is, anything that is open for discussion by all.Indeed, Kant’s term, öffentlich (“public”), has “open” (öffen) as its root meaning. Universityprofessors and students, like government officials, function as members of thepublic when they go about their daily lives. But when they carry out theirofficial duties within the Academy, members of the higher faculties function astrainers of “public servants” and are therefore answerable to thegovernment.

The secondlevel is occupied by these public servants themselves—in Kant’sscheme, the three types of “businessmen of the faculties” (pastors,lawyers, and doctors)—or for that matter, by any professional whose areaof expertise places him or her in a direct relationship with members of thegeneral public. Since the role of good government is to care for the generalwell-being of the people, Kant argues that the government has a proper duty toexercise a certain degree of control over these professionals. Laws andguidelines are quite rightly instituted for the protection of the publicagainst charlatans or incompetent practitioners. Kant states at one point thatin general, “people want to be led, that is … they want to be duped(CF 31). Since most people are susceptible tobeing deceived, the government’s job should be to protect the generalpublic as much as possible from being harmed. The more philosophicallyenlightened the general public becomes, the less strict these governmentcontrols will need to be.

In Conflict Kant connects the three higher facultiesto the three principle de­sires of ordinary people: “being happy after death, having their possessions guaranteed by pub­lic laws …, and finally, … looking forward to … health and a long life.” Thephilosopher’s message to the people ought to be that, in order for thesewishes to be fulfilled, one should “live righteously, com­mit no injustice, and, by being moderate in his pleasures and patient in hisillnesses, rely primarily on the self-help of nature.” Unwilling toaccept such strict demands, unenlightened people look to clergy, lawyers, andphysicians for miraculous help, forgetting they have “been a scoundrel all [their] life, ... broken the law, ... and abused [their] physical powers” (CF 30).[7] Since these motives are hardly ideal,they need to be regulated by any government that has the people’s bestinterests in mind. Giving the philosophy faculty freedom to criticizeeverything proposed by these educators of the professions is the best means of“governing” or “patrolling” (controlliren) the higher faculties (28).[8]

The thirdlevel is made up of what Kant called the “higher faculties”(theology, law, and medicine)—or what we today would simply call“the academic community,” excluding the philosophy faculty (and itsintellectual offspring that form departments of their own nowadays[9]). These faculties are distinctivebecause they trainthe professionals who then go out and “lead” the members of thepublic who, for one reason or another, do not wish (or are not able) to thinkfor themselves on matters of faith, justice, and health. Kant argues, famously(or infamously), that the government has both a right and a responsibility tokeep a watchful eye on any academics whose main function is to train publicservants. For if these academics are out of line, they may lead theprofessionals astray, and this, in turn, could have a directly detrimentaleffect on the general public.

The philosophyfaculty, by contrast, occupies its own distinct, fourth level precisely becauseit does not train any professionals who relate directly to the public. Instead,the academic philosopher’s main task is to engage in creative conflict with members of the higher faculties. Assuch, Kant claimed the writings and speech of philosophers ought not to be ofany concern to the government. (This means the censorship he had reluctantlycooperated with for the past four years had been inappropriate. Kant hadwillingly obeyed an unjust law.) During our discussion of these ideas at theretreat, I suddenly realized that Kant’s four-tier theory includes onefeature that is often overlooked, mainly because Kant himself does not emphasise it—though he does hint at it. Thatfeature is that these tiers can be arranged either in a straight line, likelevels or stories of a building, or in a circle. If Kant had in mind the latterarrangement, then, contrary to first impressions, the philosophy faculty hasboth the right and the responsibility to engage in direct, uninhibited contactwith the general public.What gives philosophers this right is that in their engagement with the public,philosophers do not claim some special, “higher” knowledge; rather,they appeal to one and the same faculty, “publicly” using the same“cold reason” (kalter Vernunft öffentlich) that all human beings use when thinking(CF 33).

This can beconfirmed by proposing an alternative way of picturing the relationshipsbetween the various “tiers” mentioned above, suggested byKant’s practice of referring to philosophy as the “lower”faculty in relation to the “higher” faculties that trainprofessionals. The “highness” of theology, law, and medicine,connotes a royal calling, a direct link to the “high officials” ofgovernment. The “lowness” of philosophy, by contrast, connotes adirect link with the general public. There are no professional philosophers. Rather, the philosopher’s job isto convey to the general public the views being promoted by the higherfaculties (as sanctioned by whatever is “politically correct” atthe time) in a way that will enable those who are willing to think forthemselves to make up their minds in an informed yet impartial manner. That is,the academic philosopher is (or should be) like the general public’s spy, strategically positioned at the heartof the university in order to collect information and serve as thepublic’s most reliable informant.

The problem isthat academic philosophers nowadays do tend to regard themselves as forming a distinct profession(aside from being professional teachers). As a result, they often pay allegiance to universityadministrators in a manner not unlike the way Kant thought the members of thehigher faculties ought properly to pay allegiance to the government, at leastin their public pronouncements. (Kant thought all academics, whether in thehigher or lower faculties, should be free to say whatever they wish, as long asthey are speaking only to each other, not to the general public.) The verycomponent of the university that ought to be its independent voice ofconscience is all too often just a safe haven for half-witted thinkers to makea comfortable living. If philosophy teachers view themselves as public servantsemployed by the government to produce other professionals like themselves, thenthey are actually seeing themselves as members of what Kant called the“higher faculties” and would thereby be subject to governmentcontrol in Kant’s scheme.

Kant’sargument boils down to this: in those cases where a government employsphilosophers, as when they teach in a publicly funded university, they areserving a function not unlike the “loyal opposition” in aconstitutional monarchy such as England. Good government depends on thepresence of an opposing voice that is given total freedom to say what it deemsbest for each situation; and the same is true for professional education. Thephilosopher, in Kant’s scheme, is the proper person to serve this role,because philosophers answer only to the voice of reason. Academic philosopherswho work in state-sponsored or private[10] institutions are indirectly performingpublic service through the influence their research and teaching have onmembers of the higher faculties; nevertheless, they are not bound by the samerestrictions as those who perform direct public service, because of the special position they occupyas the “lower faculty.” This applies as much to philosophers whowork within the confines of a university as it does to those who step outsidethe university and attempt to reason in a “free and open” manner,unencumbered by thefetters of grades and other limitations of the university context.Philosophical practitioners must be careful not to place themselves in“high places,” where their appeal to reason could be compromised byofficial (e.g., governmental or organizational) intervention.

In light ofthis interpretation of Kant’s position, Kant’s personal choice toabide by the will of the censor surely does not merit moral condemnation. Thatis, he was not doing anything that contradicted his own teachings on moralgoodness. However, his decision is also not worthy of praise. For it lacked thevery courage that Kant himself thought should be the hallmark of the truephilosopher, the courage to stand up to officials (whether they be governmentor university based) and openly challenge rulings that are in error.Apparently, he thought that in his case such a struggle would not be worth theeffort. Perhaps he excused himself on the grounds of old age, reasoning that hecould simply write what he wished to write on the topic and arrange to have itpublished posthumously, if he were to die before the king. Kant’scompliance, therefore, is nothing to be overly concerned about; but it isdefinitely nothing to hold up as an example for others to follow, especially sinceit fails to implement his own ideals regarding the philosopher’sresponsibilities to the general public. Although Kant in his old age failed toexhibit the moral courage of Socrates, he cannot be accused of going to theopposite extreme and selling his soul to the devil in the manner of Faust.

 

3.The Perspectival Interpretation as a Basis for Interpreting Kant’s Conflict

In addition todiscussing Kant’s views on the relationship between philosophers and thegeneral public, participants at the July 2002 CIPHER retreat addressed avariety of more specific issues regarding the proper interpretation ofKant’s philosophy of religion, in light of the interpretive guidelinesprovided in Conflict.Rather than reporting on those details here, however, I shall now take a stepback and look at the overall structure of Kant’s philosophical System inhopes of revealing its suitability to serve as a foundation for an affirmativeapproach to theology and religion.

Theorganization of Conflict,like that of most books Kant wrote after 1780, is determined by Kant’sdeep belief that philosophy is at its best when it follows an“architectonic” approach.[11] By this he meant philosophers shouldseek to construct their arguments in an orderly way determined by reasonitself, rather than following the merely random approach of collectinginformation from the “aggregate” we find in experience.Kant’s interpreters, especially those who adopt the traditionalinterpretation,[12] have almost universally rejected this“art of constructing systems”[13] as ludicrous, to the extent that anyportion of Kant’s System that an interpreter fails to understand tends tobe cast aside on the grounds that it was supposedly “only necessarybecause of the artificial requirements of Kant’s architectonic.”

The first andforemost aim of my work on Kant has been to demonstrate how mistaken this apriori rejection of architectonic reasoning is—at least, for anyinterpreter whose first aim is to understand Kant on his own terms. Withoutadopting the writer’s assumptions, an interpreter cannot hope tounderstand what the writer meant to convey, especially with a thinker as deepand complex as Kant. In this section I shall summarize how this trend can becountered by adopting precisely the opposite assumption regarding the relationshipbetween Kant’s architectonic and the various conundrums in his mainphilosophical writings: where apparent contradictions or incoherencies arise, Iattempt to discern how a clearerarticulation of the architectonic can resolve the problem. This method enablesus to see concord in the otherwise apparentlyconfusing labyrinth of Kant’s System, and so also, as we shall seeat the end of this section, in the disparate loose ends of the Conflict text.

Mostinterpreters would agree that the most fundamental presupposition ofKant’s entire philosophical System is the “Copernican”hypothesis: the claim that “we can know a priori of things only what we ourselves putinto them” (CPR Bxviii).Yet very few are aware that this hypothesis is part and parcel in Kant’smind of the assumption that philosophy must be architectonic. If philosophersmust view objects of knowledge as conforming to the forms of thought imposed onobjects by the knowing subject, and if these thought forms are by nature logical, then the resulting philosophicalknowledge will obviously be expressed according to logically ordered patterns,artistically arranged around an idea of the whole—i.e., they will displaywhat Kant calls “architectonic unity.” This establishes what I callthe overarching “Copernican Perspective” in Kant’s System, aPerspective that informs each Critique at the deepest level.[14] Interpreters who fail to recognize thatKant presents this hypothesis not as “the final solution,” but as aperspective that canbe extraordinarily useful for philosophers to adopt, invariably neglect theimportant fact that Kant does not regard it as exclusive; in particular, Kant expects non-philosophical (e.g., scientific)knowledge to involve adopting the opposite Perspective, where the aggregate isgiven a position of priority instead. This perspectival openness should be keptin mind when we consider in §4 how Kantian philosophers can enter aprofession usually reserved for theologically-trained professionals.

Kant’sself-chosen name for his System was “Transcendental Philosophy,”[15] so the Copernican (genuinelyphilosophical) Perspective is also called the “TranscendentalPerspective.”[16] But this “idea of thewhole,”[17] otherwise known as reason’sattempt to discern its own nature and limits, manifests itself in threedistinct subject areas or “standpoints:” when we apply our minds tosearch for the ultimate limits of empirical (e.g., scientific) knowledge, weare adopting the “theoretical standpoint,” where space, time, andthe 12 categories define the limit of what we can know.[18] Beyond this limit, the human mindnaturally produces certain ideas—the three archetypal examples being God,freedom, and immortality—that must by their very nature remainunknowable. Despite being unknowable, Kant insists there are good, “heuristic”(or hypothetical) reasons for treating them (even in our theoretical reasoning)as if they relate to something real.

Kant’sreputation as a philosopher whose primary impetus in theology is negative comesmainly from his utter rejection of the traditional arguments for God’sexistence in the Critique of Pure Reasonviewed by manyinterpreters as the proper starting point of Kant’s philosophy ofreligion.[19] Yet Kant’s own understanding wasthat to make such arguments the starting point of theology is to adopt asophistical approach that could never provide the proper foundations for aliving religious faith. By proving the impossibility of all possible forms of theoretical argument,he believed he was guaranteeing, once and for all, that the atheist’sposition can never be proved as theoretically valid.[20] For Kant, the negations of thetheoretical standpoint on their own provide no foundation whatsoever fortheology or religion, but only prepare the ground for constructing a genuinely affirmativefoundation: no atheist can ever claim a religious person is being irrational bybelieving in God, since the question of God’s existence cannot be settledfrom this standpoint.

Although Kantcriticizes “practical reason” after having criticized theoretical reason, heregards this new standpoint, based as it is on freedom as the “onefact” of reason, as having primacy over the theoretical. In the secondCritique, Kant’sfirst purpose is to establish what makes an act morally good. This cannot, heargues, be determined by anything external to a human person, including theoutcome of the action. Rather, it must be determined by the conformity of theperson’s freely chosen motivating maxim(s) to the “moral law”that lies in the heart of every human person. Having explained how moralityworks, however, he goes on to consider why we should be moral, even though acting morally in thisimperfect world does not always produce the happiness we think it should. HereKant offers the first clear and explicit theological affirmation in what Iregard as his “theocentric” philosophy:[21] anyone who believes trying to be morallygood is a rational approach to life is, by that very fact, acting as if God exists. In order for their beliefsto be consistent with their actions, such persons ought therefore to believe inGod.[22]

Kant’sthird standpoint is often regarded as an afterthought by interpreters, yet Kanthimself portrays it as constituting the crowning phase of his entire System: inthe Critique of JudgmentKant argues that the opposite standpoints of nature (our causally-determined,theoretical knowledge) and freedom (our self-determined, practical action) are synthesized by various forms of existentialjudgment. Most of his attention is given to examining how our judgments ofbeauty, sublimity, and natural purposiveness succeed in combining elements ofboth the theoretical and the practical standpoints, thereby demonstrating thatnature and freedom are, in fact, united in a greater whole in the context ofreal human experiences. In a lengthy Appendix, Kant explains in considerabledetail how this provides the foundation for a “moral theology,”whereby God can be viewed not just as a deistic watchmaker, but as a livingGod, who can beencountered—albeit, symbolically—in just such forms of humanexperience as are examined earlier in the book.[23]

That theaffirmative aspects of Kant’s theology do not end here can beunambiguously discerned by any open-minded reader[24] of two of Kant’s late works, Religionwithin the Bounds of Bare Reasonand Opus Postumum.The former is adequately discussed in Chapters 6 and 7, above, and inthoroughgoing detail throughout Kant’s Critical Religion,[25] so I shall not venture to give anaccount of the details here. The one point I shall make is that Religion is probably the book that bestexemplifies Kant’s application of his twelve-fold architectonic (asdetermined by the table of categories in the first Critique) to the detailed organization of a wholebook’s arguments. In particular, the four main “perspectives”governing the argument-flow within each Critique (i.e., the transcendental, logical,empirical, and hypothetical) are clearly implied by the very titles of the fourbooks of Religion:radical evil establishes the transcendental conditions for religion; personalredemption adds the logical means of countering those limits to create meaning;social redemption through church structures gives religion real empirical powerto combat evil; and correctly distinguishing between true and false ways ofserving God puts believers in the proper hypothetical frame of mind for beinggood.[26]

In the processof working out this philosophical defense of the rational conditions for thepossibility of religion, Kant develops and applies a new and profoundly reformingtheological hermeneutic, whereby all doctrines and rituals must be interpretedas moral symbols, either directly or indirectly, in order to be meaningful.[27] When the richness of Kant’saccomplishment is fully recognized in this way, the claim of traditionalinterpreters, that he was actually attempting to do away with religion byreducing it to nothing but morality, becomes almost unbelievably ludicrous.[28] Instead, we see Kant as insistingmorality must be raisedto the level of religion in order to become a feasible human endeavor at all.That is, without embracing religion at whatever level we find ourselves in ourmoral development, the gargantuan task of obeying the moral law would have tobe given up as a lost cause.

Probably themost frequent criticism of Kant’s philosophy of religion—and thisapplies not only to the adherents of the traditional interpretation, but evento many who properly recognize the religious and theological affirmations Kantdefended throughout his writings—is that his philosophy leaves no roomwhatsoever for religious experience.[29] Firestone’s reference to my methodof interpretation as the “religious” approach[30] is apt, inasmuch as I deny this almostuniversally accepted claim. In Chapter II of KCR, I argue thatSwedenborg’s writings served as the most profound catalyst forKant’s development of the all-important Copernican Perspective, as wellas for quite a few of the revolutionary theories present in the first Critique yet mysteriously absent in Kant’swritings prior to 1764. I demonstrate that Kant’s way of dealing withSwedenborg followed the Critical approach that had been his natural way ofphilosophizing from the beginning:[31] rather than rejecting Swedenborg’smystical claims outright, Kant argues that there may have been something realand even significant happening to Swedenborg, but that his attempt to draw knowledge from those experiences is illegitimate.On this basis, I claim the entire Critical System was Kant’s attempt towork out the details of this “Critical” (theoretically limited, yetopen to practical significance) view of what mystical experience entails.

Part Four ofKCR develops and defends this claim in three ways. First, I demonstrate bycollecting passages from throughout Kant’s works not only that he himselfhad experiences that could properly be called “mystical,” but thathe gave public witness to them in his writings. Second, I argue thatKant’s Opus Postumumwas meant to fill a “gap” in the architectonic of his System byaccomplishing a double synthesis: on the one hand, to unite the MetaphysicalFoundations of Natural Science(the third book developing Kant’s theoretical standpoint) with theopposing work, Metaphysics of Morals (the third book developing Kant’s practicalstandpoint), and on the other, to unite the two opposing books in Kant’s“judicial” standpoint (namely, Critique of Judgment and Religion) by giving them both a metaphysicalexpression. This “universal metaphysics” therefore had to deal witha wide spectrum of subjects; but I have demonstrated that Kant’sapproach, whether he is dealing with the mysterious ether that the science ofhis day believed underlies all natural phenomena or with the categoricalimperative that our morality imposes on us, was existential. That is, his primary attention was onour immediate experience,and how that gives rise, at a secondary level, to all the machinations ofCritical philosophy. This, and not some wild theory that Kant was a“mystic” in any traditional or fanatical sense of the word, is allI mean by claiming that Kant’s entire philosophical System leads to anexistential heart that can best be called a “Critical mysticism.”

Keeping inmind this perspectival interpretation of Kant’s philosophy and itsaffirmative religious and theological implications, let us now return to the Conflict text to see what new light can be shedon Kant’s intentions therein. First and most obviously, the overall,threefold division of the book can now be seen as a direct reflection ofKant’s architectonic distinction between the three main standpoints ofphilosophy: theologians tend to overstep the boundaries of the theoreticalstandpoint in order to establish knowledge of God; lawyers tend to overstep theboundaries of the practical standpoint in order to determine what is legallyright; and doctors tend to overstep the boundaries of the judicial standpointin order to judge the cause of diseases and the best path back to health. Thatis, these three “higher faculties” of the university are a directreflection of the three rational standpoints philosophers must Critique whenthey adopt the Copernican/Transcendental hypothesis. The latter, therefore,corresponds directly to the lowerfaculty of the university. Its job in Kant’s System is to“govern” (controlliren)the standpoints in exactly the same manner that the philosopher’s job inthe university is to govern the pronouncements of those working in and for theother faculties. This lower faculty ought (and need) not be put under anygovernmental controls, because the government should be concerned only withthose who adopt the Perspective of the general public—what I call theEmpirical Perspective, making use of reason without first having subjected itto Critique. The higher faculties can be restricted by government regulationsbecause they all adopt this fundamentally non-philosophical Perspective. Theymust adopt this Perspective, if they are to train the professionals who will beworking directly with the general public.

This brings usback to the question whether the philosopher has any legitimate reason to comeinto direct contact with the general public in Kant’s scheme. Thediagrams shown below each relate Kant’sPerspective-plus-three-standpoints System to the higher-lower facultiesdistinction in Conflict,but in two radically different ways. Figure 1 could be called “thephilosopher’s academic role in an unenlightened society;” for inany context where the general (non-academic) public really does simply want tobe duped, the philosopher’s only hope is to begin by trying to influencethe “dupers” themselves, so they will minimize the irrationalelements in their teachings and leadings.

 

INSERTFIGURE 1 NEAR HERE

 

Figure2, by contrast, could be called “the philosopher’s public role inan enlightened society,” for in any context where a significant portionof the public has become sufficiently self-examining (i.e., Critical) to beable to adopt the Copernican Perspective on their own, the philosopher has notonly a right but a duty to step out into the public square and encourage themto do so. This, as I see it, is what has been happening for the past decade inthe Philosophical Practice movement mentioned in §1 above.

 

INSERTFIGURE 2 NEAR HERE

 

Finally, wecan now see the precise way this overview of Kant’s System assists us ininterpreting the diverse views on theology and religion portrayed in Conflict. Kant’s understanding of thenecessary conflict between philosophy and theology relates primarily (if notexclusively) to academictheology, viewed as a training ground for pastors, because of its de-moralizingtendency to cater to the inclinations of the unenlightened public. Kant sees nonecessary conflict, but rather a great deal of potential concord, between philosophy and religion, provided the latter is conceived in aproperly enlightened manner. Indeed, Kant’s willingness to affirm boththeology and religion is in exact proportion to the extent of enlightenmentthat can be expected from the general public: he remains sharply critical ofany theology and religious practice that caters to those who (whetherconsciously or unconsciously) still want to be “duped;” yet he becomes not onlyaffirmative but filled with a profound hope in a future universal concord whenreferring to any theology and religion that caters to enlightened members ofthe general public. A philosopher boldly taking an active role in the realm ofpublic religion could therefore make a significant impact. In the next sectionI shall explore the potential for practicing philosophy in a concord-orientedmanner in a religious context.

 

4. The Kantian Pastor: Two Models forPhilosophical Practice in Religion

Given the factthat theologians and philosophers often share a wide range of commonintellectual interests, I am amazed that nobody (to my knowledge) in thePhilosophical Practice movement has given attention to the possibility ofpracticing philosophy in a specifically religious context. As I argued in§1, philosophy itself, not only by its nature as the “lower”(foundational) faculty of the university, but also by its appeal to a faculty(power) of the mind that is common to all human persons, cannot be a“profession” in its own right.[32] The more philosophers around the worldcome to recognize that teaching is not the only profession philosophers canhave without giving up their status as philosophers, the more enlightened thegeneral public will become. If religion is indeed the central focus ofKant’s entire philosophical System (see note 21, above), an obviousalternative profession for Kantians would be the pastoral ministry. With thispossibility in mind, our final question is: how, if at all, is it possible forKantian philosophers to become pastors?

Beforeoffering some suggestions as to how best to answer this question, I shallintroduce one further distinction, operating in Religion as well as in Conflict, between what we can call“ideal” religion and “real” religion. The former wouldconsist of a group of people that fulfills all the requirements of Kant’s“pure moral faith” by meeting together under a simple common beliefin a mysterious divine assistance, dispensing with all the historical trappingsinvolved in defending specific religious dogmas and/or requiring members toparticipate in certain religious rituals in order to become well-pleasing toGod. This is the form of religion Kant devotes most attention to describing,yet he readily admits that it is, at this stage of human development, littlemore than a hope we can hold and attempt to approach in our own imperfect ways.[33] Real human beings, as he repeatedlystates, remain creatures of sensibility, influenced by our inclinations; aslong as this is true, most people will settle for something less than idealreligion. One of the drawbacks of the traditional interpretation is that itfails to acknowledge the realistic, pragmatic strain in Kant’s writing onreligion, where he allows for many forms of belief and practice that fall shortof the ideal, provided they prompt people to move in the right direction.

With thisdistinction in mind, we can likewise distinguish between two ways a philosophercan play an active, positive role in a religious community. The first is tojoin and support a religious group that conforms as closely as possible toKant’s ideal.Kant recognized that such examples can exist, for he includes an extendedreference to one such group as an Appendix to Conflictnotinsignificantly for my interpretation, a group that was known by the name“mystics.”[34] One of the best examples of such areligious organization nowadays is The Religious Society of Friends (Quakers).Their guiding principles are surprisingly close to Kant’s ideal:[35] no belief is required in any historicalor doctrinal claims that would then be regarded as necessary for salvation; allofficially sanctioned beliefs focus on enhancing the moral life of the members;in place of the rituals many religious believers regard as sanctioned by andtherefore pleasing to God in and of themselves, Quakers merely sit in silentworship, allowing the spiritual influence of their corporate gathering toempower them to live better (and usually this means, more self-examined) lives.The tradition is so close to Kant’s ideal (see e.g., Kant’sdefinition of “religious illusion” in R 170) that, somewhat ironically,there is no special roleleft for the philosopher to perform. The philosopher who attends can encouragethe group to follow a more rational, enlightened course in any corporateactions that are taken, but he or she can have no “professionalposition” in the group, because such positions simply do not exist. Forthis tradition strictly interprets Jesus’ admonition, that the leaders inhis Kingdom of ideal religion must not “lord it over” each other,[36] to mean no professional leadership (nopaid pastor) should be employed.

The secondoption for a Kantian who wishes to make a difference in the religious world bybringing philosophy into the public square does involve the potential for taking up aprofessional role: one who feels called to exercise a positive, e nlighteninginfluence on ordinary church-goers (most of whom will, as Kant observed,“want to be led”) could become a pastor or priest. Preferably, theKantian philosopher-pastor should be free of any and all restraints imposed by hierarchicallyorganized denominations. The most suitable church will therefore beindependent, otherwise the freedom necessary to appeal first and foremost tothe common reason of those who attend could be compromised by the need to obeythe official statutes established by the denomination’s theologians.Nevertheless, this ideal is not the only possibility. Philosophicalpractitioners could become, for example, Catholic priests or Baptist ministers,provided they are willing to live with the conflict (inner and outer) that islikely to result from adopting the standpoints of both the philosophical(Kantian) theologian and the biblical (denominational) theologian. That is, theconflict between philosophy and theology experienced in the Academy (see§2, above) is likely to be mirrored in the Kantian pastor’s own mindand/or in his or her relationship with the church hierarchy. Since Kantbelieved such conflict is healthy,it should not prevent a Kantian from being a good pastor.

Kant providesnumerous guidelines for how such a pastor can live and work in a church withoutinadvertently frustrating the philosophical goal of bringing enlightenment tothe general public. Below I outline four basic guidelines for Kantianphilosopher-pastors, based on a correlation between the topics of the fourstages in Kant’s system of rational religion and the four“principles of the invisible church” specified in Book III.[37] That these guidelines are likely toplace the philosopher-pastor in a position of conflict with certain types oftheologians will be evident to anyone familiar with the range of Christiantheologies in circulation today. Yet in my experience, they are largely consistent with the doubts many thinking laypersonsexpress about the very theologies their denomination tells them they are supposed to accept.

1. Avoid anyinterpretation of a doctrine or a ritual that would tend to lead people tobelieve they are not responsible for their own moral evil. As a corollary,discourage the people’s tendency to project their own evil on to others,especially the members of other religious traditions, for in doing so theycontradict the first principle of the true church, universality.

2. Encourage abasic trust in divine assistance, but not in such a way that the participant isled to believe that God has done or will do everything, without any activeparticipation on the part of the people. Although the latter interpretation ofgrace may be more attractive, it contradicts the second principle of the truechurch, purity of moral motivation.

3. Emphasizethe supreme importance of love,[38] both toward other members of your ownchurch, in order to establish a healthy moral community, and toward members ofother traditions or no religious tradition at all, in order to maintain goodrelations with the wider community. No other religious law can surpass this one, not even a belief in thesupreme importance of one’s own scripture or tradition, for this wouldcontradict the third principle of the true church, freedom of relation.

4. Use thebeliefs and rituals in your tradition only as tools for promoting the goal stated in (3), neverallowing them to be treated as ends in themselves. For to do the latter wouldbe to base the community’s religious life on statutes and habits that areby their very nature changeable, and this would contradict the fourth principleof the true church, the unchangeableness of the constitution.

If aphilosopher-pastor employed in a hierarchical church is ever asked by churchofficials (or the denomination’s theologians) to subordinate any of theabove principles to a prudent maxim that has been handed down by tradition, heor she will be faced with an inner conflict. The pastor as philosopher should boldly stand up to the“higher” authority and defend the principle, but as theologian, should simply obey. While the Kantiancould remain silent at this point (R 185-190), he or she must not pretend tobelieve anything that positively contradicts these basic rational principles.For to acquiesce in this way is to give up all the benefits that may arise out ofa creative conflict withtheology. The likelihood of and even the need for such a conflict is unlikelyever to pass away as long as the philosopher’s Transcendental Perspectiveand the theologian’s Empirical Perspective are seen as anything butcomplementary and mutually supporting opposites. The fact that an authoritativetheologian or church official may not see the conflict in such a positive lightshould not prevent the philosopher from speaking out in the name of freedom,risking excommunication if necessary in order to “speak the truth inlove.”[39]

Congregationsthat gather together around such essentially Kantian principles are likely tobe relatively small, especially if they attempt to practice the ideal of aleaderless religious community. For as much as we would like to believe we areliving in an “enlightened” age, we are only (at best) a littlefurther along than was the Europe of Kant’s day. Political events sinceSeptember 11, 2001, show how far we still have to go before Kant’s visionof a “kingdom of ends” (his rational, moral interpretation ofJesus’ “kingdom of heaven”) becomes a widely acceptedreality. Until such a time as philosophers are willing to take a more activerole in public discourse, and above all in the nurturing of people’s religiousdispositions through direct participation in church leadership, on bothprofessional and non-professional levels, those religious leaders who have nophilosophical training are likely to attract the largest crowds—and toresist philosophy’s creative influence on religion.

 

Appendix: A Pastor’s Reflectionson Kantian Principles for Church Government[40]

Kant described religiousservice as the celebration and nurture of a universal and ethical commonwealthunder the guidance of God. In R 131-132 he states:

… if the seed of thetrue religious faith, as it is now being publicly sown in Christendom, thoughonly by a few, is allowed more and more to grow unhindered, we may look for acontinuous approximation to that church, eternally uniting all men, whichconstitutes the visible representation of an invisible kingdom of God on earth.For Reason has freed itself,in matters which by their nature ought to be moral and soul-improving, fromthe weight of a faithforever dependent upon the arbitrary will of the expositors, and has among truereverers of religion … universally laid down the followingprinciples….

Here, as throughout Religion, Kant treats his vision as a realisticplan, applicable to real church congregations. In this Appendix aphilosophically-minded pastor of a traditional congregation— Grace NorthChurch, in Berkeley, California—reflects on how Kant’s principlesfor true religion actually workin one particular community of faith.

According to Kant, freedomlies at the foundation of human morality. Yet we each compromise our freedom byallowing our choices to be governed by “weighty” inclinationsinstead of by the lightnessof the moral law.[41] As a result, we lose our balance andfall into the depths of sin, or what Kant called “radical evil”.The Bible uses metaphors such as slavery to describe the heavy burden weexperience as a result. True religion, as a walk in the lightness of being,restores our freedom. Unlike a slave community, a true Church, in Kant’sview, comprises members who are free to choose the maxims that govern their owndecisions (e.g., R 179).

Just as our present path(what we ought to bedoing) always lies midway between the horizons of our past (what is, or has been) and future (what we hope will be), so also Kant sawmorality’s immediate vertical intersection of our path as being what either balances us orthrows us askew. When applying Kant’s insights to our own congregationsand religious practice, we should remember that Kant’s vision of peopleliving in a free moral community requires us to shave away centuries ofdistortion that have obscured the purity of Jesus’ vision of the Kingdomof Heaven. All too much of the Gospel tradition’s long history is thetale of how congregations have been seduced by empires and other power structures tobecome the very thing Jesus came to free us from.[42] Like all true Protestants, Kant wasprimarily a Critical Catholic.[43] He protested against all that would makethe catholic (“universal”) community less than catholic. Theprophetically Protestant contention is that local religious communities,together with their clergy, have been hijacked: hierarchical governments havemonopolized the councils of the people that properly belong to each localneighborhood. They have made themselves deaf to the protests of those they havehijacked.

In the midstof these conflicting voices, Kant quietly tells us how free our life in theSpirit could really be. True religion, unlike sects, does not disconnect usfrom our fellow humans: religio reconnects” souls to one another, kata holou, “according tothe whole.” In Religion Kant tells the perennial four-fold story of thesoul’s encounter with the one who, guiding his path, overcomes theimpassable mountains by the lightness of being. While we are still mired in thedark heaviness of evil, we discover to our amazement the archetype[44] in our soul of a newand better order for human living. It resides already in our heart like a seedwaiting for spring. As this inner power and focus for our will comes alive inour soul, we find ourselves turning toward it for enlightenment; it motivatesus to live freelywith others in “an association of human beings merely under the laws ofvirtue” (R 95).

National anddenominational laws are necessarily coercive. But the community we seek canonly be established without coercion. It is what Kant called, in contrast toall other societies, “an ethical commonwealth.” “Woe,”he wrote, “to the legislator who wishes to establish through force a polity directed to ethicalends!”[45] Only in a community ofsouls freely dedicated to the freedom and welfare of all their neighbors, can aneffective religious standpoint be established, let alone begin to operate. Oncewe come together in such a non-coercive yetethical fellowship the end of this sequence of experience, according to Kant,is the harvest of a free, joyous and outgoing service to the world by everymember of this truly free congregation.

As we have learnt to rejoicein the light that shines in the darkness of our own soul; so we now, in friendship with a community of free souls, go forthto shine in the darkness of the world. Building such a network of congregationsis a universal duty (R 89), “a duty which is sui generis, not of men toward men, but of the humanrace toward itself.” As a prophetic minister of universal religion,preparing our various denominational traditions to undergo a complete baptism,Kant has led us “bare” (blossen) to the font of grace. Within thecatholic boundaries of bare reason, we may refresh our will to build acommonwealth that runs counter to the oppressions of society.

To conveyKant’s principles of church government[46] to those who attend Grace North Church,I use virginityas a metaphor for spiritual integrity (or oneness). It denotes the soul and those communities of souls whohave learnt to resist the weight of evil and submit only to what sets themfree. Chastity is then understood asthe political virtue of guarding the freedom and oneness of a virgin communitythrough an emphasis on the purity ofeach person’s responsibility and moral agency. The biblical prophets usedthese metaphors to inspire a self-enslaved people to work for liberty in acontext where the upper classes of thebody politic had silenced the critical voices of the lower classes. Likewise, the preachers in the ecclesiasticalestablishment of Kant’s day were hardly listening to and nurturing thevoices of a free people; perhaps this is why he argued for the necessity of atrue church, yet chose not to attend a “visible church” himself.

InReligion,Kant allowed no substitute for the uncoerced coming together of morallymotivated souls in a freely covenanted commitment to work together for theKingdom of Heaven: “AChurch … as the union of many, requires a public covenant.”[47] In the Congregationaltradition of Grace North Church the obligation that ties us together is notCredal, but Covenantal. Inorder to be unchangeable,its free agreement must be grounded not in theological belief but in an act of commitment. The stories of Israel andJesus are about fidelity to covenants undertaken freely, not submission to anideology. Unlike most Christian traditions that are based on the globalideology of a theological creed, the Congregational tradition of ecclesiasticalpolity has a philosophical (practically rational) grounding in localobligation. In both Jesus and Kant we findthis same emphasis on agreement as acting together for a purpose: to prepare for the coming of the Kingdom of Heaven.[48]

A religious covenant is anact of will whereby the covenanting parties agree to submit their will to thewill of God.[49] Such covenants lay noideology upon the local community. They simply bind us to start together fromwhere we find ourselves in our local situation. Cults cast an illusion ofglobal salvation that tends to devalue the local. They globalize by de-localazing.They offer “knowledge” in a way that excludes the life-givingunknown. Covenants, however, localize without needing to de-globalize. Theyrecognize that the hard labor of building an ethical commonwealth cannot butinvolve a quest for justice, and justice requires honoring the global (theuniversal and unchangeable aspects of the Gospel) as well as the local (thepurity and freedom of the congregation).

The Kingdom of Heaven cannotbe achieved by violence or coercion. The way to it can only be governedpeaceably. The nature of both the way and the end is therefore to gatherfriends. If a congregation be not governed by a spirit of friendship, it cannotbe religious. A local community of grace is a gathering of friends united bytheir mutual commitment to God. Although covenants are not creeds, they radiatefaith and rich sets of beliefs that can be shared by all rational people. Aslocal, they can be entered into by folk of any theological disposition. Byrefusing to submit to external coercion and choosing to fulfill our obligationsas if they were divine commands, we enter a moral order of friendship where thefree bond of love between the covenanted parties becomes the model for allhuman cooperation.

Incontrast to the coercive ways of human monarchies, the “royalpriesthood” of a pure community professes only to submit to the king whois crucified. For his Spirit speaks to us not of monopoly and tyranny, but offriendship and creativity. There is no coercion among friends. Like a truemonarch, the pastor therefore represents the royal priestliness of every soul.Celibacy is the political virtue that governs the attitude of those entrustedwith presiding over the people as they make their decisions. In a free andmoral community every voice must be cherished and heard. But whoever heads thecommunity must refrain from making decisions. He or she must be politicallycelibate. Without political celibacy, genuine priesthood is compromised and collapsesinto a monopoly. The whole community is both sovereign and priestly. The onlyvalid governing role for the pastor is to enhance the priestliness andsovereignty of each soul, both within their community and beyond. Therefore theby-laws of GNC make clear that although every parishioner has a vote in theQuarterly Parish Meeting, those in the roles of the Lay Moderator or the clergymay not vote. They are required to be celibate—a total reframing of thecatholic practice of celibacy.

All communities are at risk of beinghijacked by those who want to monopolize power. But “this all-surpassingpower is from God and not from us.”[50] If we are serious about paving the wayto implement a transformation of religion according to Kant’s vision,then political celibacy (of the lay head of the congregation and the clergy) isthe only way to preserve the freedom needed for every voice to be heard. Kantsaw how the coercive ecclesiastical and monarchic governments of his dayoppressed the lightness of being inherent in a natural, rational, and universalreligion. If the purity of the congregation (its virginity) is respected by thelistening and learning of a celibate clergy that guarantees that every voice isgiven due hearing and consideration—then a Copernican Revolution willtake place in the local practice of church government. The clergy will revolvearound the laity, not vice versa. Such a transformation of the ecclesiasticalscene, with power rising from the local level and radiating abroad in anon-coercive way, is in strict accordance with Kant’s vision. It quietlyfloods the top-down structures that dominate us, submerging them in the risingtide of a global ethical commonwealth. We, in our Kantian congregation inBerkeley, all refugees from hierarchical denominations, can testify that thispolity not only works but generates a most extraordinary experience of thatlightness of being that religious people call grace.

[51]



[1] The paper, “Perspectives inCounseling: Kantian Categories and Jungian Types as Models for PhilopsychicInsight;” can be accessed from the “articles” page of my website.

[2] Information on the Hong Kong PhilosophyCafé, including summaries of many past meetings, is available on my website.

[3] “CIPHER” stands for“Center for Insight into Philosophic Health, Education, andRenewal.” For further information on the meaning of this term as itapplies to the retreat center, see the relevant pages on my web site.

[4] I take “public servant” torefer to any professional employed and/or regulated by the government in a roleintended to be beneficial to the general public. The other two standardfaculties in the universities of Kant’s day were those of law andmedicine, whose task involved the training of lawyers and doctors,respectively. These other two areas, discussed in Parts II-III of Conflict, were not considered in any depth at theretreat, nor will they be in this essay.

[5] See CF 10n. For a detailed defense andelaboration of Kant’s claim, see Chapter VIII of my book, Kant’sCritical Religion: Volume Two of Kant’s System of Perspectives (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2000); hereafterabbreviated as KCR.

[6] Green’s essay (Chapter 8, above)alludes to the fact that Kant has often been criticized for apparently breakinghis 1794 promise to the king, never again to publish or speak on matters ofreligion or theology. The supposition is that Kant was thereby breaking his ownmoral principle, the categorical imperative. However, I see no reason to doubtKant’s own straightforward explanation of the situation in CF 10n. (For amore detailed description of the censorship issue, and a response to the grossmisrepresentations of Kant that have been perpetrated in this regard, see KCR132n, 192-193n.) Theclaim I make below is not that Kant contradicted his own principles by publishingagain on thesetopics, but that he shirked a fundamental responsibility of the philosopher byagreeing so readily to obey the edict in the first place.

[7] See also CF 35 and passim. Whereas Kant encourages philosophers tohave the courage to act inpublic (see e.g., 28-29),members of the higher faculties can act only“officially”—that is, on the public.

[8] Unfortunately, Gregor translates thiskey word simply as “control.” But the point is not thatphilosophers tell members of the other faculties what to do; rather it is thatwe observe their reasoning,very much in the way the border patrol checks passports before letting aforeigner into the country.

[9] Today’s universities have manymore faculties and departments, most concerned with training particular typesof professionals. Most of what we call the Arts and Humanities would have comeunder the Philosophy Faculty in Kant’s day, as would any academic pursuitthat was not intendedto lead directly to a profession other than university teaching.

[10] When relating Kant’s theory to thepresent day, we must keep in mind that Kant wrote Conflict at a time when Prussia was a monarchy.In modern democratic societies a privately funded university can be regarded as having virtually thesame relationship to government as a publicly funded institution, because in ademocracy, “the people” (including, of course, those supporting theprivate institution) technically are the government.

[11] For a detailed discussion of the meaningof “architectonic,” see KCR, Appendix III.2-3. I attempt to laybare the precise form taken by Kant’s architectonic as he applies it tohis own philosophical System in §§III.2-4 of Kant’s Systemof Perspectives: An Architectonic Interpretation of Kant’s CriticalPhilosophy (Lanham:University Press of America, 1993); hereafter abbreviated as KSP.

[12] As defined in §1 of theIntroduction to this volume.

[13] Immanuel Kant, Critique of PureReason, A832/B860, tr.Norman Kemp Smith (London: The Macmillan Press Ltd., 1929), 860; hereafterabbreviated CPR.

[14] For a more detailed account of what Icall “the principle of perspective” and the details of how itoperates in Kant’s System, including a table showing over 500 places inthe first Critiquewhere Kant uses terms that can be taken as equivalent to“perspective.” see KSP, Chapter II. Chapter III then explains howthis relates to Kant’s Copernican hypothesis and how Kant’sfavorite architectonic patterns develop directly out of this assumption.

[15] See e.g., Pr 279. Later, in a footnoteto the same work, Kant explains the meaning of “transcendental” ina way that confirms its existential (or “mystical,” in a new and specificallyCritical sense) rootingin the “fertile bathos of experience” (374).

[16] In KSP and KCR I adopt the convention ofcapitalizing any word that refers to Kant’s entire philosophical System(e.g., to all three Critiquestaken together) or to the Perspective that governs it, while leaving the sameterm uncapitalized when it refers to a specific part (or perspective) withinthis whole (e.g., to the three standpoints that each govern one of the Critiques, or to the four perspectives thatoperate within each Critique).For a detailed summary of these different levels of perspectives and a fullerexplanation of why the over-arching level is capitalized, see KSP, §II.4.

[17] CPR Bxliv.

[18] For a detailed summary and analysis ofthe systematic argument Kant constructs in his application of the theoreticalstandpoint, see KSP, Chapter VII.

[19] In Kant’s Rational Theology (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,1978), for example, Allen Wood reveals that even at this early stage in hiscareer he was tending in an anti-Kantian direction. For he evaluates theimportance of the three standard types of theoretical argument in exactly theopposite order of Kant’s own preferences. For a thoroughgoing discussionof the affirmative alternative to this approach, see KCR, Chapter IV. Specificresponses to Wood and other philosophers who reject Kant’s assumptionsabout the proper role of theoretical arguments are given in KCR, Appendix IV,entitled “How To Be A Theist Without Proving That God Exists.”

[20] See John Hare’s essay (Chapter 2,above) for an excellent argument confirming the problematic nature of atheismfrom a Kantian perspective.

[21] The precise meaning of this term isexplained in KCR, §I.3. In short, it does not mean that Kant’s mainconcern was explicitly theological (e.g., establishing certain knowledge ofGod)—for in this sense his philosophy is undoubtedly anthropocentric—butthat a deep sense of God’s presence (first as an idea, then as apostulate, then as an existential judgment, and finally as a symbolicallyexperienced reality) serves as the calm center of the “storm” thatconstitutes the Critical philosophy’s several revolutions.

[22] This interpretation of Kant’spractical argument for belief in God was first expressed in such anilluminating manner by Allen Wood, who refers to it as a “reductio adabsurdum practicum (Kant’s Moral Religion [Ithaca: Cornell University Press,1970], 25-34). Unfortunately, in his later work Wood has gradually moved awayfrom seeing any significant religious or theological affirmations in Kant.Nowadays he tends to adopt the traditional interpretation, with its assumptionthat Kant is a deist with a reductionistic view of religion, almost as if therewere no alternatives. See e.g., Wood’s article, “Kant’sDeism,” in Kant’s Philosophy of Religion Reconsidered, ed. Philip J. Rossi and Michael Wreen(Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1991), 1-21. For an exhaustive refutation of thedeistic/reductionistic interpretation, see Part Two of KCR; see alsoChristopher McCammon’s arguments against this interpretation in Chapter3, above. For a detailed account of the architectonic structure of Kant’sargument in the second Critique,see KSP, Chapter VIII.

[23] See KSP, Chapter IX, for a detailedsummary of Kant’s Critique of Judgment and its relation to his architectonic. Ifurther examine the focus Kant’s affirmative theology places on symbolismin KCR, Chapter V.

[24] By “open-minded reader” Imean, in particular, any reader who is willing to put aside all the trappingsof the traditional interpretation, and consider the possibility that Kant wasnot out to destroy all religion and theology, but might rather have beenattempting a radical philosophical reformation in these areas. Wheninterpreters stop reading negative innuendos between the lines of Kant’stext and see him instead as developing an integrated network of perspectivalarguments, theological and religious affirmations pop out on virtually everypage of Religion.

[25] KCR’s Appendix IX.2 summarizes thecontent of Religionin the form of “95 Theses;” most of these are surprisinglyconsistent with what many forward-thinking Christians actually believenowadays.

[26] See KCR, Chapter VIII, for a lengthyaccount of how these same four “stages” in Kant’s argumentcorrespond directly to the main emphases in Christianity: the OldTestament’s account of the problem of sin; the Gospels’ account ofgrace as the solution; the early church’s attempts to work out the socialimplications of grace, especially in the writings of Paul; and theReformation’s protest against many (but for Kant, not enough!) of thefalse means of pleasing God that had developed in Christian tradition. Contraryto the undefended claim made in Firestone’s essay (Chapter 7, above),Kant’s elaboration of these correspondences (i.e., the discussions of his“second experiment”) is spread throughout the four Books of Religion, not limited to Book Four. For an introductory-level summary of myargument in KCR, see The Tree of Philosophy4 (Hong Kong: PhilopsychyPress, 2000), Lectures 32-33.

[27] For an extended example, examining howKant applies this principle to prayer, see KCR, Appendix VIII. Proponents ofthe traditional interpretation of Kant’s philosophy of religioninvariably ignore the “indirect” side of this distinction. Yet thisis a crucial component of Kant’s affirmation of real, living religions:he finds any religious belief or ritual to be rationally acceptable, even if ithas no direct or literal moral meaning, provided it has the effect ofencouraging or enlivening a person’s underlying moral disposition. Thus,verbal prayer is acceptable as long as it “fan[s] into flames the cindersof morality in the inner recesses of our hearts” (Immanuel Kant, Lectureson Ethics, tr. LouisInfield [London: Methuen & Co. Ltd., 1930], 99 [English pagination]).

[28] If the reductionist interpretation is soludicrous, how did it become so popular? As Firestone argues in §1 of theIntroduction to this volume, the fact that T.H. Greene’s Introduction tothe translation of Religionpresented the reductionist interpretation as the only option is probably themain explanation for its widespread acceptance: English Kant scholars used thattranslation almost exclusively for over sixty years. In addition, I have arguedin KCR, Chapter VI, that certain features of the translation—especiallythe title—seemed calculated to give the false impression that Kant was areductionist in religion.

[29] A recent example of the seeminglyinnumerable references to this criticism appears in an article by LeslieStevenson, in The Friends Quarterly(April 2002), 85-92, entitled “Kant’s Philosophy andQuakerism.” Fortunately, Stevenson has significantly modified that claimin his essay here (see Chapter 11, above). Ronald Green’s impressivedemonstration of the profound influence Kant had on Kierkegaard renderssomewhat less incredible the suggestion that Kant himself might have beenattempting to prepare the way for a proper understanding of religiousexperience (see e.g., Chapter 8, above).

At the retreat, one of theparticipants pointed out in this regard that in Conflict Kant actually second-guessed Kierkegaardmore than is often recognized. For his view here is that a healthy conflictbetween theology and philosophy is necessary, even when ideal religion (ethicalreligion for Kant, or “Religion B” for Kierkegaard) is wellestablished. Kant seems to portray the philosopher and the theologian as twoperformers in a play, adopting different personas according to the requiredscript. Interestingly, Kierkegaard actually adopts this very approach as anexpository tool in the philosophical works he published during the first halfof his career.

[30] See §1 of the Introduction, as wellas Chapter 7, above.

[31] The standard reference to Kant’searly works as “pre-critical” is therefore highly misleading. Theproper term for this early period, I argue, is “pre-Copernican,”since there is nothing resembling the distinctively Transcendental character ofKant’s mature thinking in his writings before Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, where he analyzes and assessesSwedenborg’s work, yet from that time onwards, thisTranscendental/Copernican Perspective became central to Kant’s thinking.

[32] Though sometimes portrayed, I believedisastrously, as an attempt to make philosophy into a profession, a better wayto describe the philosophical practice movement is as an attempt to encouragephilosophers to take up professions other than teaching. Pastoral ministry is a profession thathas received little or no attention by the (largely unreligious) members ofthis movement. Yet of all professions, this one would seem to have the greatestchance of enabling philosophers to have an enlightening influence on a widespectrum of the general public.

[33] For example, Kant states in R 135n thatwe should “diligently work … even now” for “thecontinuous development of the pure religion of reason out of its present stillindispensable shell.” In the second edition he adds a second footnote,clarifying: “Not that it ‘will cease’ (for it might always beuseful and necessary, perhaps, as a vehicle) but that ‘it cancease’ … ”.

[34] See CF 69-75.

[35] Stevenson’s essay (Chapter 11,above) develops this correspondence in much greater detail.

[36] Matt. 20:25-26. Obviously, the sameadmonition could be interpreted as mandating a particular way of being a pastor, especially sinceelsewhere in the New Testament paid leadership appears to be a given. My pointhere is merely that the Quaker approach is closer to the Kantian ideal, because“priestcraft” always tends to pervert true religion (e.g., R175ff).

[37] R 101-102. The correlation between thefour Books and the four principles is no accident, for Kant based both on thesame architectonic pattern, what I have called a “second-level analyticrelation.” For an explanation of the latter, see The Tree ofPhilosophy, Lecture 13,and KSP, §III.

[38] In KCR, §§IX.2-3, I propose afull-fledged biblical theology focused on love. Such a biblical theology, Ibelieve, would minimize the negative effects of any remaining differencesbetween Kantian philosopher-pastors and biblical theologians, paving the wayfor a concord that preserves all the creative benefits of both Perspectives.

[39] Eph. 4:15. To remain quiet in the faceof a potential conflict, as Kant did throughout the mid-1790’s,ironically makes the philosopher virtually indistinguishable from thetheologian.

[40] This section is adapted from a muchlonger essay written by Rev. Richard Mapplebeckpalmer. The full text in itsoriginal form, entitled “The Copernican Revolution in Religion: ATestimony on Kantian Church Government,” can be found athttp://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/texts/KantianTestimony.htm.

[41] Thus Jesus said (Mt. 11:30): “Formy yoke is easy and my burden is light.”

[42] For a detailed interpretation ofBiblical references to such political/power issues, see Palmquist’s BiblicalTheocracy: A vision of the biblical foundations for a Christian politicalphilosophy (Hong Kong:Philopsychy Press, 1993).

[43] See KCR 239-242: Kant was at the same time a“liberalizing conservative” and a “conserving liberal.”

[44] Or “prototype” (seeJacobs’ essay, Chapter 7 of this volume).

[45] R 96 [87]; cf. Mt. 23.

[46] Universality (or “oneness”),purity, freedom, and unchangeability (R 101-102 [93]).

[47] R 105 [96]. Although the translatorsgive the word covenant,Kant’s term, Verplichtung,more literally means obligation.Kant does not use the German word for covenant, Übereinkommen; but undertaking a public obligation isusually sealed in some sort of covenant. English and German use the same word, Testament, to clarify that the stories of Israeland Jesus are alike stories about fidelity to a covenant.

[48] “The wish of all well-disposedpeople is, therefore, ‘that the kingdom of God come, that His will bedone on earth.(R 101 [92]) See Palmquist’s The Kingdom of God is at Hand!’(Did Kant Really Say That?),” History of PhilosophyQuarterly 11:4 (October1994), 421-437.

[49] Thus Jesus prayed (Mt. 6:10): “Your kingdom come, your will be done onearth as it is in heaven.”

[50] 2 Cor. 4:7.

 

 

 

This etext is based on a prepublication draft of the published version of this essay.

Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

My Web Counter identifies you as visitor number

to this page, last updated on 4 April 2011. Please come again!

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published articles.

Back to the main map of Steve Palmquist's web site.